“What Good Is Literary Criticism?” by Normal Friedman: Summary and Critique

“What Good Is Literary Criticism?” by Norman Friedman, first appeared in The Antioch Review in its Autumn 1960 issue, published by Antioch Review Inc.

"What Good Is Literary Criticism?" by Normal Friedman: Summary and Critique
Introduction: “What Good Is Literary Criticism?” by Normal Friedman

“What Good Is Literary Criticism?” by Norman Friedman, first appeared in The Antioch Review in its Autumn 1960 issue, published by Antioch Review Inc. The article, digitized by JSTOR, addresses the purpose and value of literary criticism amidst growing skepticism from various quarters, including poets, scholars, and lay readers. Friedman explores criticism’s necessity as a bridge between the reader and the deeper layers of literature, countering the notion that it over-intellectualizes or diminishes the pleasure of literary experience. He argues for a balanced approach, where reasoning and systematic inquiry coexist with emotional and imaginative engagement. Highlighting the utility of criticism in cultivating taste, extending understanding, and enhancing aesthetic appreciation, the article situates literary criticism as essential to both appreciating and challenging the complexities of creative works. It further underscores the importance of reasoning and theory in navigating the subjective and often ambiguous terrain of literary interpretation. Friedman’s work remains a cornerstone in discussions about the role of criticism in literary theory, advocating for an informed yet flexible approach to understanding literature.

Summary of “What Good Is Literary Criticism?” by Normal Friedman
  • The Age of Criticism and Growing Skepticism
    Friedman opens by identifying the contemporary era as an “age of criticism,” marked by the proliferation of analytical works and theoretical discussions in literature. However, this growth has been met with skepticism from poets, scholars, and lay readers, who view criticism as excessive, overly intellectual, and at times harmful to the creative process (“Critics do sometimes go too far, and much criticism being published today is dull, repetitive, mechanical, pedantic, and unimaginative” (Friedman, 1960, p. 316)).
  • Criticism vs. Creation: A Necessary Tension
    A recurring concern in the article is the perceived tension between literary creation and criticism. Critics such as John Crowe Ransom and T.S. Eliot lament that excessive criticism risks overshadowing creative impulses. Friedman acknowledges this tension but maintains that criticism, when properly applied, complements creativity rather than stifling it (“Criticism, in relation to creative literature, is subordinate and should remain so: critics must follow writers and not vice versa” (Friedman, 1960, p. 316)).
  • Hostility Towards Intellectual Inquiry in Literature
    Friedman identifies a broader cultural hostility towards intellectualism, tracing its roots to historical, psychological, and philosophical objections. He critiques the belief that reasoning about literature diminishes its enjoyment, arguing instead that intellectual engagement enhances rather than detracts from aesthetic pleasure (“But do we really think that our pleasures are so frail as to disappear under analysis? Or that the powers of literature are so weak as to be so easily crushed?” (Friedman, 1960, p. 319)).
  • The Role of Theory and Systematic Inquiry
    The article emphasizes the inevitability and utility of theoretical frameworks in literary analysis. Friedman argues that no interpretation occurs in a vacuum; even the most intuitive responses are shaped by implicit assumptions (“We cannot interpret it or anything about it without—deliberately or intuitively—bringing something of our past experience with life and with literature to bear upon our reading” (Friedman, 1960, p. 326)).
  • Inductive and Deductive Reasoning in Criticism
    Friedman elaborates on the role of inductive and deductive reasoning in criticism, countering the notion that these methods are antithetical to the literary experience. He asserts that both are essential to forming meaningful interpretations (“Most questions of literary interpretation … are of this second type … making inferences, and it is that process of making inferences which is … dependent upon the principles of reasoning” (Friedman, 1960, p. 322)).
  • Multiple Dimensions of Literary Criticism
    Friedman outlines the multifaceted nature of literary criticism, encompassing inquiries into the poet’s life, the poem’s structure, its effects on the reader, and its connection to the broader world. He emphasizes that no single approach can capture the entirety of a work’s significance (“No one approach gives us the whole truth; that each approach does what it was designed to do and not what any other approach can do” (Friedman, 1960, p. 325)).
  • Criticism as a Path to Discovery
    The ultimate purpose of criticism, according to Friedman, is to enable deeper understanding and appreciation of literature. By examining our assumptions and engaging rigorously with texts, critics can transcend personal biases and uncover new dimensions of meaning (“In this way only can we do justice to the poet. How else can we get outside ourselves and enter the world he took such pains to make for us?” (Friedman, 1960, p. 330)).
  • Criticism and Progress in Literary Knowledge
    Friedman asserts that criticism is not an idle exercise but a progressive endeavor. Through systematic inquiry and theoretical exploration, critics contribute to the collective understanding of literature (“Although there is no way of choosing between competing interpretations unless the issue is first joined, this doesn’t mean … that one interpretation is as good as the other” (Friedman, 1960, p. 328)).
Literary Terms/Concepts in “What Good Is Literary Criticism?” by Normal Friedman
Theoretical Term/ConceptExplanation/DefinitionReferences from the Text
Criticism vs. CreationThe tension between the act of literary creation and the critical analysis that follows, often seen as potentially stifling creativity.“Criticism, in relation to creative literature, is subordinate and should remain so: critics must follow writers and not vice versa” (p. 316).
Inductive ReasoningA form of reasoning that begins with specific observations and builds general conclusions or theories.“Induction … provides us instead with a rational method for testing its results” (p. 323).
Deductive ReasoningA logical process that starts with a general statement or hypothesis and examines the possibilities to reach a specific conclusion.“Deduction refers to the manner in which the mind infers the nature of that which is unknown” (p. 322).
Subordination of CriticismThe idea that criticism should serve creative literature, not dominate it.“Critics must follow writers and not vice versa” (p. 316).
Multiplicity of ApproachesThe acknowledgment that different works demand different theoretical and methodological approaches to interpretation.“No one approach gives us the whole truth; that each approach does what it was designed to do” (p. 325).
Reason in Literary CriticismAdvocacy for rational inquiry and reasoning as necessary tools for deeper understanding of literature.“There is no escape, then, from reason—even if we should want one” (p. 326).
Hostility to Intellectual InquiryThe resistance from some quarters to analyzing literature systematically, often tied to fears of over-intellectualization.“Critics do sometimes go too far, and much criticism being published today is dull, repetitive, mechanical” (p. 316).
Role of Theoretical FrameworksThe necessity of explicit or implicit frameworks in guiding interpretation and criticism.“We cannot interpret it or anything about it without—deliberately or intuitively—bringing something of our past experience” (p. 326).
Progress in Literary KnowledgeThe idea that criticism contributes to the accumulation of understanding and knowledge about literature.“Although there is no way of choosing between competing interpretations … one interpretation is as good as another” (p. 328).
Educational Function of CriticismThe role of criticism in extending and cultivating a reader’s taste, understanding, and appreciation of literature.“How does such an argument allow for us to develop and extend our natural responses and tastes?” (p. 327).
Contribution of “What Good Is Literary Criticism?” by Normal Friedman to Literary Theory/Theories
Theory/ApproachContributionReferences from the Article
New CriticismAdvocates for close reading and systematic analysis of texts, emphasizing internal coherence, paradox, and tension as critical tools for interpretation.“We look in poems for conflicts, paradoxes, ironies, ambiguities, symbols, and the like, in an attempt to define the total meaning” (p. 324).
Reader-Response TheoryHighlights the interaction between the text and the reader, considering the subjective experience and interpretative engagement of the audience.“How it affects him or what good or harm it will do to him” as a basis for critical inquiry (p. 325).
FormalismEmphasizes the study of the artistic structure of literature, analyzing how the parts of a literary work relate to the whole.“If we want to study the poem as an artistic product, then we must ask how the parts are related to the whole” (p. 324).
Historical-Biographical CriticismDiscusses how the poet’s life, historical context, and creative process influence the composition and interpretation of a literary work.“How a poem reflects the life and background of its author … the poem has the status of a document” (p. 324).
Psychological CriticismIntroduces psychological theories, including Freudian analysis, to understand the creative process and character motivations within literary texts.“The various psychological theories which by now have gained currency” as tools for interpretation (p. 324).
Critical PluralismAdvocates for a multiplicity of approaches to literary analysis, recognizing that no single method can provide a complete understanding of a text.“No one approach gives us the whole truth; each evolves out of a reasonable process of inference” (p. 325).
Ontology of LiteratureExplores the metaphysical nature of literary works, questioning their relationship to reality and their role in representing or shaping the human experience.“The mode of being of poetry—whether it has any significant connection with reality or whether it is simply a fictive device” (p. 325).
Educational Philosophy in CriticismAsserts the role of criticism in enhancing a reader’s aesthetic and intellectual engagement with literature, fostering growth in understanding and taste.“Criticism contributes to a liberal and enlarged area of aesthetic awareness, bounded only by our capacity for new experience” (p. 330).
Ethical CriticismDiscusses the moral implications of literature and its influence on readers, engaging with the ethical dimensions of literary texts.“What good or harm it will do to him” as part of the critical inquiry into the poem-reader relationship (p. 325).
Theory of Induction and DeductionIntegrates philosophical reasoning methods into literary criticism, demonstrating how systematic inquiry can enrich interpretation and understanding.“Deduction refers to the manner in which the mind infers the nature of that which is unknown … Induction helps us to test the adequacy of our conclusions” (pp. 322–323).
Examples of Critiques Through “What Good Is Literary Criticism?” by Normal Friedman
  • Critique of Robert Frost’s “Stopping by Woods on a Snowy Evening” (Explication Approach)
    Using Friedman’s defense of systematic analysis, critics might revisit John Ciardi’s controversial explication of Frost’s poem. A focus on paradox and tension, as Friedman suggests, could reveal the conflict between the speaker’s duty and the allure of nature’s stillness (**”We look in poems for conflicts, paradoxes, ironies, ambiguities, symbols, and the like”* (Friedman, 1960, p. 324)).
  • Critique of T.S. Eliot’s “The Waste Land” (New Criticism)
    Applying Friedman’s emphasis on internal coherence, Eliot’s work could be analyzed for its paradoxes and ambiguities, examining how the fragmentation reflects the spiritual disarray of modernity (**”If poetry is, as they say, organized around a reconciliation of opposing views … then we look in poems for conflicts and tensions”* (p. 324)).
  • Critique of F. Scott Fitzgerald’s The Great Gatsby (Historical-Biographical Criticism)
    Following Friedman’s approach to considering an author’s life and historical context, Fitzgerald’s novel could be critiqued as a reflection of Jazz Age decadence and disillusionment (**”How a poem reflects the life and background of its author … the poem has the status of a document”* (p. 324)).
  • Critique of Emily Dickinson’s Poetry (Psychological Criticism)
    Through psychological theories, Dickinson’s use of imagery and themes of death and isolation could be explored as expressions of her introspective and reclusive personality (**”The various psychological theories … allow us to infer the nature of that process from the characteristics of the results”* (p. 324)).
Criticism Against “What Good Is Literary Criticism?” by Normal Friedman
  • Overemphasis on Rationality
    Critics might argue that Friedman places excessive emphasis on logical reasoning and systematic inquiry, potentially marginalizing the emotional and intuitive responses that many believe are central to experiencing literature (**”There is no escape, then, from reason—even if we should want one”* (Friedman, 1960, p. 326)).
  • Dismissal of Anti-Critical Perspectives
    While Friedman acknowledges skepticism toward criticism, he largely dismisses it as hostility to intellectual inquiry. Critics could challenge this as oversimplifying valid concerns about over-intellectualization of literature (**”The attack on the abuses of reason frequently turns into an attack on reason itself”* (p. 317)).
  • Limited Consideration of Cultural and Social Factors
    The essay focuses heavily on individual works and theoretical frameworks but provides limited discussion of broader cultural or societal influences on literature and its interpretation, which are vital in contemporary literary studies.
  • Neglect of Reader’s Agency in Interpretation
    Although Friedman addresses reader-response aspects, his approach could be critiqued for insufficiently emphasizing the role of individual readers’ diverse contexts, experiences, and subjective interpretations.
  • Insufficient Engagement with Non-Western Perspectives
    The essay operates predominantly within a Western literary tradition and critical frameworks, leaving non-Western literary theories and perspectives unexamined, thus limiting its inclusivity.
  • Overgeneralization of Critical Pluralism
    While Friedman advocates for multiple approaches, critics might argue that his emphasis on critical pluralism lacks specificity, as it does not fully address how competing interpretations should be prioritized or reconciled (**”No one approach gives us the whole truth”* (p. 325)).
  • Perceived Elitism in Literary Study
    Friedman’s argument for intellectual rigor and systematic approaches might be criticized as catering to an academic elite, alienating casual readers and undermining literature’s accessibility.
Representative Quotations from “What Good Is Literary Criticism?” by Normal Friedman with Explanation
QuotationExplanation
“Criticism, in relation to creative literature, is subordinate and should remain so: critics must follow writers and not vice versa.” (p. 316)Friedman highlights that criticism serves creative literature, ensuring that it complements rather than stifles the artistic process.
“Critics do sometimes go too far, and much criticism being published today is dull, repetitive, mechanical, pedantic, and unimaginative.” (p. 316)This acknowledges valid critiques of literary criticism, stressing that poorly executed criticism can harm the appreciation of literature.
“The attack on the abuses of reason frequently turns into an attack on reason itself.” (p. 317)Friedman defends intellectual inquiry against those who dismiss it outright, asserting the importance of reasoning in understanding literature.
“No one critical theory as to the nature and function of literature should dominate the field, for artists must be allowed to work out their own visions and revisions.” (p. 316)He advocates for diversity in critical approaches, warning against rigid adherence to a single critical framework.
“We cannot interpret it or anything about it without—deliberately or intuitively—bringing something of our past experience with life and with literature to bear upon our reading.” (p. 326)This emphasizes the inescapable influence of personal and cultural contexts in interpreting literary works.
“Logic merely formulates what happens whenever we think effectively, just as grammar merely formulates what happens whenever we speak or write effectively.” (p. 323)Friedman underscores that reasoning is a natural part of critical thought, comparable to how grammar structures language.
“If you can’t feel it, then I can’t explain it to you” … undercuts the entire teaching profession at its roots.” (p. 327)He critiques the anti-intellectual stance that denies the role of teaching and systematic inquiry in fostering deeper literary appreciation.
“There are systems and there are systems—some are closed in that they limit our experience of a poem … some are open in that they widen our experience by suggesting ways of asking questions.” (p. 329)Friedman distinguishes between restrictive and expansive critical methods, advocating for those that enhance exploration and understanding.
“The poem does not interpret itself for us, and we cannot interpret it … without bringing something of our past experience with life and with literature to bear upon our reading.” (p. 326)He asserts that interpretation requires active engagement and is shaped by the reader’s experiences and knowledge.
“We are all critics, then, whether we know it or not.” (p. 329)Friedman democratizes the concept of criticism, suggesting that forming opinions and judgments is an inherent human activity.

Suggested Readings: “What Good Is Literary Criticism?” by Normal Friedman

  1. Friedman, Norman. “What Good Is Literary Criticism?” The Antioch Review, vol. 20, no. 3, 1960, pp. 315–30. JSTOR, https://doi.org/10.2307/4610268. Accessed 16 Nov. 2024.
  2. Butler, Christopher. “What Is a Literary Work?” New Literary History, vol. 5, no. 1, 1973, pp. 17–29. JSTOR, https://doi.org/10.2307/468405. Accessed 16 Nov. 2024.
  3. Fleming, Bruce E. “What Is the Value of Literary Studies?” New Literary History, vol. 31, no. 3, 2000, pp. 459–76. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/20057615. Accessed 16 Nov. 2024.
  4. Showalter, Elaine. “Literary Criticism.” Signs, vol. 1, no. 2, 1975, pp. 435–60. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/3173056. Accessed 16 Nov. 2024.

“Humanism and the Scientific Worldview” by David E. Cooper: Summary and Critique

“Humanism and the Scientific Worldview” by David E. Cooper first appeared in Theoria: A Journal of Social and Political Theory (June 1999, No. 93), published by Berghahn Books in collaboration with the University of KwaZulu-Natal.

"Humanism and the Scientific Worldview" by David E. Cooper: Summary and Critique
Introduction: “Humanism and the Scientific Worldview” by David E. Cooper

“Humanism and the Scientific Worldview” by David E. Cooper first appeared in Theoria: A Journal of Social and Political Theory (June 1999, No. 93), published by Berghahn Books in collaboration with the University of KwaZulu-Natal. This essay explores the complex relationship between humanism and science, contending with the perceived antagonism between the two. Cooper traces the philosophical evolution of humanism, distinguishing between various interpretations, such as Renaissance humanism, rational subjectivity, and existential humanism. He posits that modern humanism, particularly in its existential form, inherently challenges the scientific worldview by rejecting notions of an objective reality independent of human perspectives. This work is significant in literature and literary theory as it underscores the philosophical tensions between human agency, cultural heritage, and the epistemological frameworks underpinning scientific inquiry. It invites a rethinking of humanism’s role in shaping intellectual discourses and its implications for understanding human culture and values amidst modernity’s scientific advancements.

Summary of “Humanism and the Scientific Worldview” by David E. Cooper

1. Diverse Interpretations of Humanism and Science

  • Cooper highlights contrasting views on humanism and its relation to science, citing some who see science as irrelevant to the humanities, while others equate modern humanism with scientific humanism (Cooper, 1999, p. 1). These differences stem from varying definitions of humanism and its historical contexts.

2. Renaissance Humanism and its Legacy

  • Renaissance humanism, focused on the humanities (litterae humaniores), is identified as the origin of the term. It emphasized cultural and intellectual pursuits, setting itself apart from modern interpretations tied to secular and scientific concerns (Cooper, 1999, p. 2).

3. Evolution into Philosophical Humanism

  • Cooper traces how modern philosophical humanism diverges from its Renaissance roots, transitioning into a worldview that often conflicts with scientific perspectives. This conflict arises when humanism prioritizes subjective, human-centered values over scientific objectivity (Cooper, 1999, p. 3).

4. Characterizing Humanism

  • Cooper identifies four dominant characterizations of humanism in intellectual history:
    1. Essentialism: Positing a universal “essence” of humanity (Cooper, 1999, p. 4).
    2. Naturalism: Viewing humans as a natural species, often aligned with scientific explanations (Cooper, 1999, p. 6).
    3. Rational Subjectivity: Celebrating the autonomy and rational capacities of individuals (Cooper, 1999, p. 8).
    4. Existential Humanism: Emphasizing human agency in constructing meaning and reality, rejecting universal truths (Cooper, 1999, p. 11).

5. The Critique of Humanism

  • Modern critiques of humanism often focus on its anthropocentric tendencies and its reliance on human-centered metaphysics, which some environmental ethicists and philosophers like Heidegger argue has contributed to ecological and epistemic crises (Cooper, 1999, p. 5).

6. Existential Humanism as the Dominant Form

  • Cooper identifies existential humanism as the most representative form of contemporary humanism. It denies a fixed, objective reality, emphasizing instead the constructive role of human agency in shaping the world (Cooper, 1999, p. 12).

7. Historical Continuity and Divergence

  • Cooper connects existential humanism to its Renaissance precursors, who, in response to medieval skepticism about divine order, began privileging human agency and practical engagement over metaphysical speculation (Cooper, 1999, p. 13).

8. Implications for Science and Humanism

  • Cooper argues that existential humanism inherently conflicts with the scientific worldview when the latter asserts an independent, intrinsic reality. This clash reflects deeper tensions between human-centered values and objective scientific inquiry (Cooper, 1999, p. 15).

9. Bridging Historical and Popular Understandings

  • The dual heritage of humanism—as both a celebration of human culture and a naturalistic concern for human well-being—explains the divergent popular interpretations of the term today (Cooper, 1999, p. 16).
Theoretical Terms/Concepts in “Humanism and the Scientific Worldview” by David E. Cooper
Theoretical Term/ConceptDefinition/ExplanationReference in Text
HumanismA worldview emphasizing human values, culture, and agency. Varied interpretations exist, including philosophical, scientific, and cultural humanism.Discussed throughout; historical roots in Renaissance humanism (Cooper, 1999, pp. 1-2).
Renaissance HumanismFocus on humanities (litterae humaniores), cultural achievements, and skepticism toward universal scientific truths.Origin of humanism, contrasting with modern forms (Cooper, 1999, p. 2).
EssentialismThe belief in a universal human essence that defines human nature. Often criticized for being overly simplistic.Rejected by modern humanists like Sartre; “existence precedes essence” (Cooper, 1999, pp. 4-5).
NaturalismA view that positions humans as part of nature, often rejecting supernatural explanations.Explored in the context of scientific humanism (Cooper, 1999, pp. 6-7).
Rational SubjectivityThe notion that humans are autonomous, rational beings capable of independent judgment and creating meaning.Rooted in Enlightenment ideas; critiqued for privileging individual rationality (Cooper, 1999, pp. 8-9).
Existential HumanismEmphasizes human agency in shaping reality and meaning. Rejects objective truths independent of human perspective.Argued to be the dominant modern form of humanism (Cooper, 1999, pp. 11-13).
Scientific WorldviewA perspective that seeks to explain reality through objective, empirical, and naturalistic methods.Often conflicts with existential humanism (Cooper, 1999, p. 15).
AnthropocentrismThe belief that humans are the central or most significant entities in the universe.Criticized by environmental ethics and linked to ecological issues (Cooper, 1999, pp. 5-6).
Metaphysical HubrisThe overconfidence in human ability to define or reshape reality based solely on human perspectives and interests.Critiqued by thinkers like Heidegger and Nagel (Cooper, 1999, p. 12).
Self-AssertionA response to the loss of divine order, emphasizing human agency and practical engagement with the world.Highlighted as a response to medieval skepticism (Cooper, 1999, p. 13).
Agency-Driven AntirealismThe view that reality is shaped by human practices, desires, and interests rather than existing independently.Central to existential humanism (Cooper, 1999, p. 11).
Post-Enlightenment SkepticismDoubts about the universal applicability and objectivity of reason and scientific inquiry.Rooted in critiques of Enlightenment rationality (Cooper, 1999, p. 9).
Environmental EthicsCritiques humanism’s anthropocentric tendencies and its perceived role in ecological degradation.Views humanism as responsible for a “technological stance” towards nature (Cooper, 1999, pp. 5-6).
Contribution of “Humanism and the Scientific Worldview” by David E. Cooper to Literary Theory/Theories
  • Critique of Anthropocentrism in Literature and Culture
    • Cooper critiques the anthropocentric focus of humanism, which literary ecocriticism also addresses. He aligns with environmental ethics that challenge human-centered narratives, suggesting a shift towards perspectives that decentralize human agency in interpreting texts and culture (Cooper, 1999, pp. 5-6).
  • Existential Humanism and Poststructuralist Theory
    • By emphasizing existential humanism, Cooper contributes to theories like poststructuralism, which reject fixed meanings and universal truths. His discussion parallels Derrida’s notion of deconstruction, where meaning is shaped by human agency rather than inherent essences (Cooper, 1999, pp. 11-12).
  • Reinterpretation of Enlightenment Values
    • Cooper interrogates rational subjectivity as rooted in Enlightenment ideals, critiquing its dominance in Western thought. This resonates with postcolonial and feminist literary theories that challenge universal rationality as a colonial or patriarchal construct (Cooper, 1999, p. 8).
  • Skepticism Toward Universal Truths
    • Cooper’s alignment with Renaissance skepticism about “global truths” connects with New Historicism, which views meaning and interpretation as context-dependent, influenced by historical and cultural factors (Cooper, 1999, pp. 2-3).
  • Human Agency in Shaping Reality
    • His focus on agency-driven antirealism informs reader-response theory. Cooper’s view that humans construct reality aligns with the idea that readers co-create meaning through their subjective engagement with texts (Cooper, 1999, p. 11).
  • Humanism’s Role in Technological Narratives
    • Cooper critiques humanism’s complicity in technological and ecological degradation, offering insights relevant to Marxist and materialist theories. These theories examine how human-centered ideologies influence cultural production and consumption (Cooper, 1999, pp. 5-6).
  • Influence on Ecocritical Theory
    • By addressing humanism’s impact on ecological crises, Cooper aligns with ecocriticism, which critiques literature’s anthropocentric biases and promotes more inclusive representations of nature (Cooper, 1999, pp. 5-6).
  • Reevaluation of Renaissance Humanism
    • His analysis of Renaissance humanism’s focus on cultural achievements enriches literary studies by highlighting how these traditions inform modern humanist and posthumanist perspectives (Cooper, 1999, pp. 13-15).
  • Intersection with Modern Literary Theories
    • Cooper’s existential humanism, with its emphasis on human agency and constructed realities, contributes to phenomenological approaches in literary theory, where subjective experience is central to understanding texts (Cooper, 1999, pp. 11-12).
Examples of Critiques Through “Humanism and the Scientific Worldview” by David E. Cooper
Literary WorkCritique Based on Cooper’s IdeasKey References from Cooper’s Article
Mary Shelley’s FrankensteinCritique of anthropocentrism: Victor Frankenstein’s attempt to “master nature” reflects humanism’s technological hubris.Cooper discusses the “technological stance” and its ecological consequences (Cooper, 1999, pp. 5-6).
Joseph Conrad’s Heart of DarknessPost-Enlightenment skepticism: The novella critiques Enlightenment rationality and its link to colonial exploitation.Cooper critiques rational subjectivity and universal truths rooted in Enlightenment ideals (Cooper, 1999, pp. 8-9).
Ralph Waldo Emerson’s NatureCritique of human agency in shaping reality: Emerson’s transcendentalism embodies existential humanism but risks anthropocentrism.Cooper’s existential humanism focuses on human agency shaping the world, often critiqued for anthropocentrism (Cooper, 1999, p. 11).
William Blake’s Songs of Innocence and ExperienceCritique of human dualism: Blake’s works challenge humanism’s compartmentalization of innocence and experience, advocating a holistic view.Cooper discusses skepticism toward rigid humanist categories and fixed essences (Cooper, 1999, pp. 4-5).
Criticism Against “Humanism and the Scientific Worldview” by David E. Cooper
  • Lack of Practical Solutions
    • While Cooper critiques anthropocentrism and the scientific worldview’s conflicts with humanism, he provides limited practical alternatives to reconcile these tensions.
  • Overgeneralization of Philosophical Traditions
    • The categorization of humanism into essentialism, naturalism, rational subjectivity, and existential humanism may oversimplify complex and diverse philosophical traditions.
  • Insufficient Engagement with Counterarguments
    • Cooper critiques the scientific worldview and Enlightenment rationality but does not fully address the strengths or potential synergies between science and humanism.
  • Limited Representation of Modern Humanism
    • The discussion heavily emphasizes existential humanism as the dominant form, potentially sidelining other significant contemporary interpretations of humanism, such as pragmatic humanism.
  • Ambiguity in Defining Existential Humanism
    • While Cooper highlights existential humanism’s emphasis on agency and constructed realities, the boundaries of this concept remain vague and open to interpretation.
  • Neglect of Posthumanist Perspectives
    • Cooper’s critique of traditional humanism does not sufficiently engage with posthumanist theories that challenge human exceptionalism and offer alternative frameworks.
  • Inconsistent Historical Connections
    • The link between Renaissance humanism and existential humanism, while compelling, may oversimplify historical developments and downplay transitional philosophical movements.
  • Limited Scope in Addressing Ecological Concerns
    • Although Cooper critiques anthropocentrism, his work lacks depth in proposing how humanism can adapt to address pressing ecological and environmental crises.
Representative Quotations from “Humanism and the Scientific Worldview” by David E. Cooper with Explanation
QuotationExplanation
“The appearance of a necessary opposition between humanism and science is illusory.”Cooper highlights how the perceived conflict between humanism and science is rooted in misunderstandings of their roles and definitions, showing how they may complement rather than contradict each other.
“Modern humanism just is scientific humanism.”This reflects Cooper’s observation of modern humanist movements aligning themselves with scientific rationality, advocating for a worldview grounded in empirical evidence.
“Humanism, in the dominant philosophical sense today, is antagonistic to the scientific worldview.”Cooper argues that contemporary philosophical humanism often challenges the deterministic and objective claims of science, emphasizing subjective human values and agency.
“The scientific worldview implies that reality is independent of human perspectives and purposes.”This contrasts with existential humanism, which Cooper identifies as centered on the idea that reality is shaped by human interaction and interpretation.
“The theory of the subject is at the heart of humanism.”Cooper points to the focus on human subjectivity and autonomy as central to humanist philosophy, especially in its existential variant.
“Existential humanism denies that there is a way the world intrinsically is, independent of human perspectives.”Here, Cooper encapsulates existential humanism’s anti-realist stance, emphasizing the role of human agency in constructing reality.
“Human dignity is secured not through success in contemplative appreciation of the cosmic order, but through successful coping with the world.”This reflects the shift from metaphysical or religious humanism to a pragmatic approach, emphasizing human ability to adapt and thrive.
“For Heidegger, the technological stance to the world as equipment at human disposal is responsible for ‘the devastation of the earth.’”Cooper integrates Heidegger’s critique of anthropocentrism, linking humanism’s focus on agency with environmental exploitation.
“Renaissance humanism engendered, in more than one way, the development of a natural science which left little space for the divine and supernatural.”Cooper examines how Renaissance humanism’s focus on human capacity and reason laid the groundwork for scientific inquiry and secularism.
“There is no one position under attack and inviting a single characterization.”Cooper acknowledges the multiplicity of critiques against humanism, arguing for a nuanced understanding of its diverse interpretations and implications.
Suggested Readings: “Humanism and the Scientific Worldview” by David E. Cooper
  1. Cooper, David E. “Humanism and the Scientific Worldview.” Theoria: A Journal of Social and Political Theory, no. 93, 1999, pp. 1–17. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/41802111. Accessed 16 Nov. 2024.
  2. McNeill, William H. “History and the Scientific Worldview.” History and Theory, vol. 37, no. 1, 1998, pp. 1–13. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/2505637. Accessed 16 Nov. 2024.
  3. Paden, Roger. “Foucault’s Anti-Humanism.” Human Studies, vol. 10, no. 1, 1987, pp. 123–41. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/20008991. Accessed 16 Nov. 2024.
  4. Griffioen, Sander. “ON WORLDVIEWS.” Philosophia Reformata, vol. 77, no. 1, 2012, pp. 19–56. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/24710030. Accessed 16 Nov. 2024.

“Literary Theory, Criticism, and History” by Rene Wellek: Summary and Critique

“Literary Theory, Criticism, and History” by René Wellek first appeared in The Sewanee Review in Winter 1960, published by Johns Hopkins University Press.

"Literary Theory, Criticism, and History" by Rene Wellek: Summary and Critique
Introduction: “Literary Theory, Criticism, and History” by Rene Wellek

“Literary Theory, Criticism, and History” by René Wellek first appeared in The Sewanee Review in Winter 1960, published by Johns Hopkins University Press. In this seminal article, Wellek distinguishes the interrelated but distinct fields of literary theory, criticism, and history. He advocates for their collaboration, emphasizing that literary theory involves the principles and criteria of literature, criticism deals with the interpretation and evaluation of individual works, and history examines literature in its temporal and cultural contexts. Wellek critiques efforts to subsume these disciplines into one or reduce them to purely historical or critical endeavors, defending the necessity of theoretical inquiry in understanding literature as a systematic art form. The work remains a cornerstone in literary studies, urging a balanced approach to evaluating literature’s aesthetic, historical, and theoretical dimensions. This piece underscores the importance of integrating these perspectives to enrich the study and appreciation of literary works, advancing the broader discourse in humanities.

Summary of “Literary Theory, Criticism, and History” by Rene Wellek

Key Themes and Insights:

  1. Distinction of Literary Disciplines
    Wellek emphasizes the differentiation among literary theory, literary criticism, and literary history, asserting their interdependence but distinct roles. Literary theory explores the principles and criteria of literature, criticism interprets and evaluates works, and history situates literature in its historical context (pp. 1-3).
  2. Collaboration Between Disciplines
    Wellek argues that the three disciplines—literary theory, criticism, and history—“implicate each other so thoroughly as to make inconceivable literary theory without criticism or history, or criticism without theory or history” (p. 2).
  3. Critique of Terminological Confusion
    The article critiques the terminological inconsistencies across languages. For example, the German term “Literaturwissenschaft” retains a broad meaning, while English terms like “literary theory” and “poetics” have narrower or misleading connotations (pp. 3-4).
  4. Theory’s Role in Literary Studies
    Literary theory is positioned as vital to understanding literature as a systematic and intellectual pursuit. Wellek defends theory against efforts to subordinate it to history or criticism (p. 5).
  5. Response to Northrop Frye
    Wellek acknowledges Northrop Frye’s contributions to literary theory but critiques Frye’s attempt to isolate literary theory as the supreme discipline while diminishing the roles of criticism and history (pp. 6-7).
  6. Rejection of Pure Historicism
    Wellek refutes extreme historicism, which he sees as overly relativistic and prone to antiquarian pedantry. He argues for integrating history into literary analysis without reducing literature to historical artifacts (pp. 8-10).
  7. Defending Close Reading
    While acknowledging the flaws of close reading, Wellek asserts its indispensability for advancing literary understanding, calling it a fundamental tool for interpretation (p. 11).
  8. Against Absolute Relativism
    Wellek criticizes complete relativism, arguing that it leads to skepticism and undermines meaningful evaluation. He advocates for a balanced approach that recognizes universal aesthetic values while accounting for historical and cultural contexts (pp. 14-15).
  9. Vision for Unified Literary Study
    Wellek concludes by advocating a unified literary approach where theory, criticism, and history coexist and inform each other. He likens literature to an “imaginary museum” that transcends time and space, asserting humanity’s defiance of impermanence (pp. 18-19).
Theoretical Terms/Concepts in “Literary Theory, Criticism, and History” by Rene Wellek
Term/ConceptDefinition/ExplanationKey Reference/Explanation in Text
Literary TheoryThe study of principles, categories, and criteria of literature; the systematic framework for understanding literature.“Literary theory” is the study of the principles of literature, its categories, criteria, and the like (p. 2).
Literary CriticismAnalysis and evaluation of specific literary works; focuses on interpretation and judgment of individual texts.“Literary criticism” (primarily static in approach) is distinct yet related to literary theory and history (p. 2).
Literary HistorySituates literature within historical and cultural contexts, analyzing its evolution and chronological order.“History” examines literature as a series of works arranged in a chronological order and as integral parts of the historical process (p. 2).
HistoricismThe approach that emphasizes understanding literature within its historical and cultural context, often critiqued for relativism.Critiqued for leading to “antiquarian pedantry” and devaluing the universal aspects of art (pp. 8-10).
Close ReadingA detailed, focused analysis of a text’s structure and meaning, emphasizing the text itself over external context.“Close reading… is surely here to stay, as any branch of knowledge can advance and has advanced only by careful inspection” (p. 11).
Systematic KnowledgeLiterature studied as a coherent system, with its principles and values interconnected.“A theory of literature… must ultimately aim at systematic knowledge about literature” (p. 5).
RelativismThe belief that judgments and values are context-dependent and subjective; critiqued for undermining universal evaluation.Extreme relativism “leads to paralyzing skepticism, to an anarchy of values” (p. 14).
Collaboration of DisciplinesThe interdependence of theory, criticism, and history to provide a comprehensive understanding of literature.“These distinctions are fairly obvious… yet the disciplines implicate each other thoroughly” (pp. 1-3).
Aesthetic StandardsUniversal principles for evaluating the quality of literary works, countering pure relativism.“Critical judgment requires aesthetic standards just as ethical or logical standards are indispensable” (p. 15).
Imaginary MuseumA metaphor for the cumulative and transcendent nature of literature across time and cultures.“Literature… is a chorus of voices… articulating defiance of impermanence, relativity, and history” (p. 19).
Contribution of “Literary Theory, Criticism, and History” by Rene Wellek to Literary Theory/Theories

Theoretical FrameworkContributionReference/Key Argument in Article
StructuralismEmphasizes the systematic nature of literature, arguing for the analysis of its intrinsic structure and coherence.“Literary theory… must ultimately aim at systematic knowledge about literature” (p. 5).
Formalism/New CriticismDefends close reading as essential for understanding literature, focusing on the text itself over historical or biographical details.“Close reading… is surely here to stay, as any branch of knowledge can advance… only by careful, minute inspection” (p. 11).
Historicist CriticismChallenges reductive historicism while advocating for integrating historical context without subsuming literature entirely into history.“History cannot absorb or replace theory, while theory should not even dream of absorbing history” (p. 19).
Comparative LiteratureAdvocates for breaking down linguistic and cultural barriers to create a universal understanding of literature.“We can more directly and easily assemble our museum in a library… still faced with the walls and barriers of languages” (p. 19).
Reader-Response TheoryImplicitly supports the interaction between the critic and the text, emphasizing judgment and interpretation by the reader.“The critic must analyze, interpret, and evaluate it; he must, in short, be a critic in order to be a historian” (p. 14).
Aesthetic TheoryCritiques relativism and reasserts the need for universal aesthetic standards for evaluating literature.“There is a hierarchy of viewpoints… evaluation grows out of understanding: correct evaluation out of correct understanding” (p. 17).
Interdisciplinary Literary StudiesProposes collaboration between literary theory, criticism, and history to enrich literary analysis and interpretation.“The three disciplines… implicate each other thoroughly, making inconceivable one without the others” (p. 2).
Philosophical HermeneuticsAddresses the role of the critic’s subjectivity and argues for objective standards to counteract extreme relativism.“Men can correct their biases… rise above temporal and local limitations, aim at objectivity, arrive at some knowledge and truth” (p. 14).
Canon FormationEngages with the debates around the literary canon, arguing for the acknowledgment of universally recognized classics.“There is… a very wide agreement on the great classics: the main canon of literature” (p. 16).
Universal HumanismAdvocates for the universality of literature, asserting that works from diverse cultures resonate with shared human experiences.“There is a common humanity which makes every art remote in time and place… accessible and enjoyable to us” (p. 18).

Examples of Critiques Through “Literary Theory, Criticism, and History” by Rene Wellek
Literary WorkType of CritiqueApplication of Wellek’s ConceptsReference from Article
Milton’s PoetryEvaluation and ranking of works based on their intellectual and aesthetic richness.Wellek critiques the rejection of value judgments in Frye’s Anatomy of Criticism, emphasizing that Milton offers deeper intellectual engagement than lesser poets like Blackmore.“Milton is a more rewarding and suggestive poet to work with than Blackmore” (p. 6).
Shakespeare’s PlaysBalancing historical context with intrinsic textual analysis for interpretation.Wellek critiques pure historical readings that ignore a work’s intrinsic values, emphasizing the interplay between history and criticism in understanding Shakespeare.“We cannot simply interpret Hamlet in terms of the hypothetical views of Shakespeare or his audience” (p. 15).
Marvell’s “Horatian Ode”Historical context as a supplementary tool for understanding, not as definitive.Discussing Cleanth Brooks’s interpretation, Wellek shows how historical information aids textual understanding while maintaining the poem’s autonomy as a work of art.“The poem has to be read as a poem… historical evidence cannot finally determine what the poem says” (p. 7).
Herbert’s “Sacrifice”Critique of misinterpretations stemming from arbitrary or speculative readings.Wellek highlights the need for a balance between historical context and textual fidelity, critiquing Empson’s overly speculative analysis of Herbert’s poem.“Miss Tuve seems right in insisting that ‘I must climb the tree’ means only ‘I must ascend the cross'” (p. 9).
Criticism Against “Literary Theory, Criticism, and History” by Rene Wellek
  1. Ambiguity in Defining Disciplinary Boundaries
    While Wellek emphasizes the distinctions among literary theory, criticism, and history, critics argue that his definitions are sometimes vague and that these disciplines are more fluid in practice than he acknowledges.
  2. Overemphasis on Systematic Knowledge
    Critics of structuralist or formalist approaches might argue that Wellek’s focus on “systematic knowledge” risks reducing literature to abstract principles, neglecting its emotional, cultural, and individual significance.
  3. Limited Engagement with Postmodern and Non-Western Perspectives
    Wellek’s framework heavily relies on Western aesthetic and philosophical traditions, potentially marginalizing postmodern theories or non-Western literary approaches.
  4. Resistance to Radical Historicism
    While Wellek critiques extreme historicism, some scholars argue that his stance underestimates the importance of socio-political and cultural contexts in shaping literature.
  5. Dismissal of Relativism
    Wellek’s critique of relativism is seen by some as overly rigid, dismissing the valuable insights that historical and cultural relativism can provide in understanding diverse literary traditions.
  6. Neglect of Reader-Response and Subjectivity
    His focus on systematic and objective analysis has been criticized for neglecting the subjective experience of readers and the variability of interpretations across audiences.
  7. Potential Hierarchization of Literary Disciplines
    Critics suggest that Wellek implicitly prioritizes theory over criticism and history, despite his stated intention to treat all three disciplines as equally significant.
  8. Resistance to New Theoretical Trends
    Wellek’s arguments appear rooted in mid-20th-century literary debates, potentially limiting their relevance to later theoretical developments such as post-structuralism and feminist theory.
  9. Insufficient Attention to Popular or Marginalized Literatures
    His focus on canonical works and “great classics” has been criticized for excluding popular, marginalized, or experimental literary forms from scholarly consideration.
Representative Quotations from “Literary Theory, Criticism, and History” by Rene Wellek with Explanation
QuotationExplanation
“Literary theory is the study of the principles of literature, its categories, criteria, and the like.”This defines literary theory as the systematic exploration of the structures and norms that govern literature, laying a foundation for analytical and evaluative approaches in literary studies.
“Literary theory without criticism or history, or criticism without theory or history, or history without theory and criticism, is inconceivable.”Wellek emphasizes the interdependence of the three disciplines, arguing that they are essential and inseparable for a holistic understanding of literature.
“The term ‘literary theory’ is preferable to ‘science of literature’ because ‘science’ in English has become limited to natural science.”Wellek critiques the term “science of literature” for its misleading implications, preferring “literary theory” as it better encapsulates the humanistic and evaluative aspects of studying literature.
“Criticism is conceptual knowledge, or aims at such knowledge. It must ultimately aim at systematic knowledge about literature, at literary theory.”Criticism, for Wellek, is not mere opinion but a structured, systematic pursuit of knowledge that contributes to the development of literary theory.
“A literary work of art is a verbal structure of a certain coherence and wholeness.”This quotation reflects Wellek’s formalist leanings, asserting that literature must be studied as a coherent verbal artifact, independent of external biographical or historical contexts.
“The assumption of one eternal, narrowly defined standard had to be abandoned…but complete relativism is equally untenable.”Wellek rejects both absolutism and extreme relativism, advocating for a balanced approach that recognizes enduring aesthetic standards while allowing for historical and cultural variability.
“Close reading has led to pedantries and aberrations…but it is surely here to stay.”While acknowledging the limitations and excesses of close reading, Wellek defends its necessity as a methodological cornerstone of literary analysis.
“History cannot absorb or replace theory, while theory should not even dream of absorbing history.”Wellek underlines the distinct but complementary roles of history and theory, advocating for their collaborative yet independent contributions to literary studies.
“Evaluation grows out of understanding: correct evaluation out of correct understanding.”This highlights Wellek’s belief in the foundational role of interpretive accuracy in making sound evaluative judgments about literature.
“Literature…is a chorus of voices—articulate throughout the ages—which asserts man’s defiance of time and destiny.”Wellek celebrates the timeless and universal nature of literature, portraying it as a collective human achievement that transcends historical and cultural boundaries.
Suggested Readings: “Literary Theory, Criticism, and History” by Rene Wellek
  1. Wellek, René, and Rene Wellek. “Literary Theory, Criticism, and History.” The Sewanee Review, vol. 68, no. 1, 1960, pp. 1–19. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/27540551. Accessed 16 Nov. 2024.
  2. Rowlett, John L., editor. “Reviewing Criticism: Literary Theory.” Genre Theory and Historical Change: Theoretical Essays of Ralph Cohen, University of Virginia Press, 2017, pp. 122–36. JSTOR, https://doi.org/10.2307/j.ctt1v2xtv6.12. Accessed 16 Nov. 2024.
  3. Galinsky, Hans. “Literary Criticism in Literary History: A Comparative View of the ‘Uses of the Past’ in Recent American and European Histories of American Literature.” Comparative Literature Studies, vol. 1, no. 1, 1964, pp. 31–40. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/40245625. Accessed 16 Nov. 2024.
  4. TOBER, KARL. “THE MEANING AND PURPOSE OF LITERARY CRITICISM.” Colloquia Germanica, vol. 1, 1967, pp. 121–41. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/23980066. Accessed 16 Nov. 2024.

“From Literary Theory to Critical Method” by Rita Felski: Summary and Critique

“From Literary Theory to Critical Method” by Rita Felski first appeared in Profession in 2008, published by the Modern Language Association.

"From Literary Theory to Critical Method" by Rita Felski: Summary and Critique
Introduction: “From Literary Theory to Critical Method” by Rita Felski

“From Literary Theory to Critical Method” by Rita Felski first appeared in Profession in 2008, published by the Modern Language Association. This seminal work challenges the traditional structure and focus of literary theory courses, advocating for a greater emphasis on critical methods that shape literary analysis. Felski critiques the conventional “theory course” model for its tendency to prioritize philosophical and political alignments over methodological clarity, arguing that this often obscures the mechanics of interpretation essential for advanced academic work, particularly for graduate students. By highlighting the interplay between theoretical frameworks and interpretative practices, Felski underscores the importance of making implicit analytical choices explicit, ultimately equipping scholars with the tools to refine their research methodologies. This piece has been pivotal in shifting literary studies from rigid theoretical orthodoxy to a more nuanced understanding of how disciplines evolve through practical and methodological adaptation. Its insights remain significant for both literary theory and pedagogy, emphasizing the dynamic and interdisciplinary nature of textual interpretation.

Summary of “From Literary Theory to Critical Method” by Rita Felski
  1. Significance of Literary Theory in Academia
    • Felski emphasizes that literary theory, once criticized for detracting from the appreciation of primary texts, has become an essential component of academic curricula. It introduces students to intellectual trends spanning decades (“Theory can no longer be dismissed as an arcane subspecialty”, p. 108).
    • However, traditional courses focus excessively on theoretical frameworks, neglecting the methodological tools essential for practical analysis (“the conventional theory course…tends to obscure rather than illuminate issues of method”, p. 108).
  2. Critique of Conventional Course Structures
    • The typical structure of theory courses categorizes content by political or philosophical alignments, such as Marxism, deconstruction, feminism, and postcolonial theory (“grouping course materials according to criteria of philosophical orientation or political affiliation”, p. 108).
    • Felski argues that such organization reflects how theories present themselves, often overlooking the practical application of methods (“literary theory is something of a misnomer, given that the dominant figures in the theory canon are typically concerned not just with literature”, p. 109).
  3. Interplay of Theory and Method
    • A critical gap exists between theoretical principles and their application in literary studies. While theories often reshape reading practices, interpretation remains grounded in established techniques (“practices of reading…covertly mold how theories are interpreted”, p. 111).
    • Close reading, a hallmark of New Criticism, persists across ideological divides, whether in traditional analysis or queer theory (“Critics…can share a common commitment to specific styles of interpretation”, p. 110).
  4. Call for Critical Method Courses
    • Felski advocates for courses emphasizing critical methods to complement theory courses. These courses would highlight interpretative techniques and methodological decisions (“a course in critical method thus offers a valuable complement to the standard theory class”, p. 108).
    • Such an approach helps students refine their research projects by focusing on how expansive theoretical claims translate into specific analytical strategies (“Thinking seriously about critical method cannot help but alter our view of literary studies”, p. 108).
  5. Challenges to Theoretical Orthodoxy
    • Felski critiques the rigidity of certain theoretical approaches, noting that methodological preferences often transcend political or philosophical commitments (“the relations between political or philosophical worldviews and methods of reading are complex”, p. 111).
    • She highlights the persistence of traditional practices even among scholars committed to radical theories (“the impact of new theoretical pictures on actual reading practices is more attenuated, mediated, and unpredictable”, p. 112).
  6. Interdisciplinary Implications
    • Disciplinary conventions heavily shape how theories are employed. For instance, literary scholars analyzing non-literary texts often adapt methods from their training (“Victorianists may pride themselves on stretching the boundaries…yet to outsiders their arguments…unequivocally proclaim their English department training”, p. 113).
    • Felski underscores the necessity of acknowledging these conventions rather than aspiring to a supposed disciplinary transcendence (“the transcendence of disciplinarity…turns out to be more apparent than real”, p. 113).
  7. Teaching Methodological Awareness
    • A critical methods course emphasizes the procedural choices underpinning literary arguments, enabling students to articulate and justify their analytical approaches (“students…gain the ability to justify their evidentiary claims against skeptical or hostile criticism”, p. 115).
    • It also bridges divides between disparate theoretical perspectives by focusing on shared interpretative practices (“such intellectual cross-fertilization…guards against reinventing the methodological wheel”, p. 115).
  8. Conclusion: Rethinking Literary Studies
    • Felski concludes by advocating for a shift from abstract theoretical debates to the practical application of critical methods. This shift enriches the discipline by integrating the habitual, procedural knowledge that defines literary scholarship (“we need to think more carefully and more amply about how disciplinary training…shapes what we know and how we know it”, p. 116).
Theoretical Terms/Concepts in “From Literary Theory to Critical Method” by Rita Felski
Theoretical Term/ConceptDescriptionReference/Context in the Article
Literary TheoryA broad field examining literature through various philosophical, political, and cultural lenses.Described as encompassing New Criticism, structuralism, feminism, Marxism, postcolonial theory, and more, often organized around political or philosophical affiliations (p. 108-109).
Critical MethodAnalytical techniques and interpretive frameworks used in literary studies.Advocated as a complement to theory courses, emphasizing “how expansive claims… are translated into forms of interpretation” (p. 111).
Close ReadingDetailed, text-focused analysis that uncovers meaning through linguistic and structural features.Identified as a shared technique across theoretical divides, including New Criticism and queer theory (p. 110).
Symptomatic ReadingA method uncovering hidden contradictions or repressed meanings in texts.Explored in the context of feminist and Marxist critique, highlighting its assumptions about implicit or repressed textual meanings (p. 114-115).
Reflection TheoryThe idea that literature reflects societal structures, ideologies, and realities.Critiqued as an intellectually shaky premise regardless of the political or theoretical stance of its advocates (p. 115).
Ideology CritiqueExamination of how texts perpetuate or challenge dominant ideologies.Discussed in the context of alternatives to ideology critique and the “hermeneutics of suspicion” (p. 114).
Hermeneutics of SuspicionA skeptical interpretative approach that assumes hidden meanings or power structures in texts.Referenced as part of recent critiques in literary studies, contrasting with emerging interest in affect and enchantment (p. 114).
DisciplinarityThe influence of academic disciplines on methodologies and arguments.Highlighted as shaping literary interpretation through ingrained practices rather than theoretical claims (p. 113).
Interdisciplinary StudiesIntegration of methods from multiple academic disciplines.Explored in relation to cultural studies, Victorian studies, and broader academic interactions that reveal disciplinary habits (p. 113-114).
New CriticismA literary approach focusing on the intrinsic features of texts, such as form and structure.Recognized for its lasting influence on interpretative techniques like close reading, even in poststructuralist contexts (p. 111).
Queer TheoryA framework analyzing texts through the lens of sexuality and gender, often challenging norms.Cited alongside traditional approaches for shared interpretative methods, despite ideological differences (p. 110).
Feminist CritiqueAnalyzing texts with a focus on gender, power relations, and representation.Examples include divergent approaches like Foucauldian historicism versus psychoanalytic frameworks (p. 110).
Cultural StudiesAn interdisciplinary field examining cultural texts and practices in their sociopolitical contexts.Referenced in debates about methodological overlap and tensions with literary studies (p. 113).
PoststructuralismA theory questioning stable meanings, emphasizing the instability of language and interpretation.Discussed as part of the broader theoretical spectrum shaping contemporary literary studies (p. 109).
PhenomenologyA philosophical approach focusing on subjective experience and perception.Contrasted with materialist-historicist perspectives, especially in discussions on reader engagement (p. 114).
FormalismAn approach emphasizing form and structure over historical or ideological content.Explored in various contexts, including the resurgence of formalist techniques in Marxist and other theoretical frameworks (p. 115).
Anti-antimimesisA response to antimimetic approaches, reasserting the significance of representation in texts.Included in course discussions of alternatives to historicist and ideological critiques (p. 114).
Contribution of “From Literary Theory to Critical Method” by Rita Felski to Literary Theory/Theories
  • Critique of Theoretical Rigidity
    • Felski challenges the dominance of rigid theoretical frameworks, advocating for a more fluid integration of theory and method.
    • She highlights how theoretical affiliations often overshadow methodological choices, which are crucial for nuanced literary analysis (“predictable groupings give way to less familiar constellations and affinities”, p. 111).
  • Emphasis on Methodology in Literary Studies
    • The article underscores the importance of critical methods in complementing traditional theory courses.
    • It argues that methodologies offer a transformative lens, refining both analysis and interpretation in scholarly work (“Thinking seriously about critical method cannot help but alter our view of literary studies”, p. 108).
  • Revisiting Close Reading
    • Felski repositions close reading as a versatile technique that transcends ideological boundaries, bridging traditional critics and postmodern theorists.
    • This observation revitalizes its relevance in contemporary literary studies (“The technique of close reading defines the work…but it also characterizes the writings of queer theorists”, p. 110).
  • Expanding Symptomatic Reading
    • She revisits symptomatic reading, a method often associated with Marxist and psychoanalytic critiques, questioning its assumptions and applications.
    • By exploring its nuances, Felski offers a fresh perspective on how implicit or “repressed” meanings are identified in texts (“Why is a text imagined as containing ruptures, contradictions, or fissures?”, p. 115).
  • Critique of Ideology Critique and Hermeneutics of Suspicion
    • The article examines the limitations of ideology critique and the hermeneutics of suspicion, advocating for alternative interpretative frameworks.
    • This critique fosters new ways of thinking about literature beyond political or ideological constraints (“efforts to imagine alternatives to ideology critique and the hermeneutics of suspicion”, p. 114).
  • Integration of Formalism in Diverse Theories
    • Felski highlights how formalist methodologies persist within Marxist, feminist, and queer critiques, promoting intellectual cross-fertilization.
    • This contribution encourages scholars to acknowledge methodological overlaps across theoretical divides (“Marxist criticism, in many of its variants, is highly formalist in orientation”, p. 115).
  • Reassessment of Interdisciplinary Practices
    • By addressing the disciplinary influences on literary studies, Felski prompts a re-evaluation of how fields like cultural studies intersect with traditional literary scholarship.
    • This perspective broadens the scope of interdisciplinarity, emphasizing its methodological, not just thematic, implications (“Disciplinary preferences shape readings not only of literary works but also of theoretical texts”, p. 113).
  • Contribution to Poststructuralism
    • Felski critiques poststructuralism’s tendency to overemphasize language and instability, urging a balanced approach that considers interpretative practices.
    • This fosters a practical application of poststructuralist ideas without neglecting textual and methodological consistency (“practices of reading…covertly mold how theories are interpreted, taken up, and used”, p. 111).
  • Reflection on the Role of Theory in Practice
    • The work bridges the gap between theoretical abstractions and their practical implementation in literary studies.
    • Felski’s emphasis on integrating theory with methodological practices reshapes how scholars approach research and pedagogy (“The goal…is to infuse students with an awareness of the variety and complexity of methodological choices”, p. 114).
  • Advancing Literary Pedagogy
    • By proposing courses on critical methods, Felski contributes to the evolution of literary pedagogy, ensuring that students develop both theoretical knowledge and analytical skills.
    • This pedagogical shift encourages students to articulate and refine their interpretative strategies (“make explicit what is often left implicit…to make students more aware of interpretative choices”, p. 116).
Examples of Critiques Through “From Literary Theory to Critical Method” by Rita Felski
Literary WorkCritique Through Felski’s LensKey Reference/Concept from Felski
Sherlock Holmes Stories by Arthur Conan DoyleCatherine Belsey’s critique of Sherlock Holmes using symptomatic reading highlights contradictions and implicit meanings.Felski uses this as an example to explore the assumptions behind symptomatic reading, such as textual ruptures or repressed meanings (p. 115).
Heart of Darkness by Joseph ConradScholars often claim theoretical affiliations (e.g., Deleuze or Stuart Hall) but default to traditional interpretation methods.Felski critiques the tendency of theoretical preambles to mask unchanged interpretative practices (p. 112).
Victorian Novels (e.g., works by Charles Dickens)Victorianists extend their field by addressing themes like social reforms but still rely on English department training methods.Felski critiques disciplinary habits influencing interpretations, even in interdisciplinary contexts (p. 113).
Texts from Queer Theory Canon (e.g., Eve Kosofsky Sedgwick’s works)Close reading, a traditional New Critical method, is applied to queer theory to reveal nuanced textual and contextual insights.Felski highlights the methodological overlap between traditional and radical critical approaches, like queer theory (p. 110).
Criticism Against “From Literary Theory to Critical Method” by Rita Felski
  • Overemphasis on Methodology Over Theory
    Critics argue that Felski’s emphasis on critical methods may downplay the transformative power of theoretical frameworks, which often challenge entrenched ideologies and practices.
  • Undermining the Autonomy of Literary Theory
    By suggesting that critical methods often shape theoretical interpretations, Felski is seen by some as diminishing the philosophical depth and autonomy of literary theory.
  • Risk of Fragmenting Literary Studies
    The focus on diverse methodologies and the rejection of rigid theoretical categories could exacerbate the already noted fragmentation of literary studies, making it harder to find common ground among scholars.
  • Limited Engagement with Non-Western Theories
    Felski’s work has been critiqued for predominantly addressing Western literary theories and methodologies, with limited reference to global or non-Western perspectives.
  • Ambiguity in Defining Critical Method
    While advocating for critical method courses, Felski provides a broad and somewhat vague definition of “method,” leaving room for debate about its practical application and scope in literary studies.
  • Potential Undervaluation of Political Critique
    By critiquing the hermeneutics of suspicion and ideology critique, Felski risks sidelining the importance of political engagement in literary analysis, which many scholars view as vital to the discipline.
  • Reliance on Established Academic Traditions
    Felski’s recognition of ingrained disciplinary practices may be perceived as conservative, inadvertently reinforcing existing academic norms rather than challenging them.
  • Generalization of Methodological Practices
    Critics argue that her discussions on shared methodologies, such as close reading, risk oversimplifying the distinct epistemological aims of different theoretical schools.
Representative Quotations from “From Literary Theory to Critical Method” by Rita Felski with Explanation
QuotationExplanation
“Theory can no longer be dismissed as an arcane subspecialty.”Felski asserts the significance of theory in contemporary intellectual life, illustrating its pervasive influence beyond academia, such as in media and popular culture. This challenges the earlier perception of theory as niche or irrelevant.
“Thinking seriously about critical method cannot help but alter our view of literary studies.”This highlights Felski’s core argument that focusing on methodologies transforms how literary studies are practiced and perceived, bridging theoretical abstractions and interpretive practices.
“The technique of close reading defines the work of apolitical or traditionally minded critics… but it also characterizes the writings of queer theorists.”Felski demonstrates that critical methods like close reading transcend ideological divides, uniting diverse theoretical camps through shared analytical tools.
“A course in critical method thus offers a valuable complement to the standard theory class, yet its function is not just additive but also transformative.”Felski emphasizes the transformative potential of critical method courses, which encourage students to engage deeply with interpretative strategies rather than merely adding to theoretical knowledge.
“Practices of reading…covertly mold how theories are interpreted, taken up, and used.”This highlights the reciprocal relationship between theory and practice, showing how methodologies shape the application and evolution of theoretical frameworks.
“Critics at opposite ends of the theoretical spectrum… can share a common commitment to specific styles of interpretation.”Felski challenges the idea that theoretical divides result in completely divergent practices, instead pointing to methodological overlaps that unite critics across ideological boundaries.
“Modes of reading, like other habitual activities, are often deeply ingrained in the form of practical rather than theoretical knowledge.”This underscores the importance of practice in literary studies, where interpretative habits are often transmitted implicitly through teaching and mentorship rather than formal instruction.
“Disciplinary training… shapes what we know and how we know it.”Felski critiques the unconscious influence of disciplinary conventions, which shape scholarly arguments and interpretations regardless of theoretical allegiances.
“Literary theory thus expands students’ intellectual horizons beyond the category of literature.”Felski highlights the interdisciplinary nature of literary theory, which connects literature with broader themes like history, politics, and identity, enriching students’ academic experience.
“The goal…is to make explicit what is often left implicit and to make students more aware of interpretative choices.”This encapsulates Felski’s pedagogical focus, advocating for courses that illuminate the often-hidden assumptions and decisions underpinning literary analysis.
Suggested Readings: “From Literary Theory to Critical Method” by Rita Felski
  1. Felski, Rita. “From Literary Theory to Critical Method.” Profession, 2008, pp. 108–16. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/25595888. Accessed 16 Nov. 2024.
  2. Fessenbecker, Patrick. “Content and Form.” Reading Ideas in Victorian Literature: Literary Content as Artistic Experience, Edinburgh University Press, 2020, pp. 39–75. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.3366/j.ctv136c554.7. Accessed 16 Nov. 2024.
  3. CULLER, JONATHAN. “Introduction: Critical Paradigms.” PMLA, vol. 125, no. 4, 2010, pp. 905–15. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/41058288. Accessed 16 Nov. 2024.
  4. Margolis, Joseph. “The Threads of Literary Theory.” Poetics Today, vol. 7, no. 1, 1986, pp. 95–110. JSTOR, https://doi.org/10.2307/1772090. Accessed 16 Nov. 2024.

“What Is the Meaning of a Text?” by Jeffrey Stout: Summary and Critique

“What Is the Meaning of a Text?” by Jeffrey Stout first appeared in 1982 in New Literary History, Vol. 14, No. 1, under the thematic issue “Problems of Literary Theory.”

"What Is the Meaning of a Text?" by Jeffrey Stout: Summary and Critique
Introduction: “What Is the Meaning of a Text?” by Jeffrey Stout

“What Is the Meaning of a Text?” by Jeffrey Stout first appeared in 1982 in New Literary History, Vol. 14, No. 1, under the thematic issue “Problems of Literary Theory.” Published by Johns Hopkins University Press, this influential article scrutinizes the very question of textual meaning and challenges the premise that seeking a definitive answer to “What is the meaning of a text?” is a productive endeavor. Instead, Stout proposes that such an inquiry might mislead interpreters by focusing on an abstract and ambiguous concept rather than on practical interpretative questions. By examining the hermeneutical and theoretical assumptions surrounding textual meaning, Stout contends that discussions about meaning are often convoluted and, at times, unresolvable. He suggests that interpretative theory would benefit from focusing on authorial intention or contextual significance rather than an elusive “meaning.”

Stout’s argument holds significance in the fields of literature and literary theory because it advocates a pragmatic approach to interpretation, resonating with Quine’s idea of “explication as elimination.” This pragmatic view emphasizes the utility of interpretation over the search for an essential meaning. Stout’s work influenced subsequent debates in hermeneutics, moving away from essentialist definitions of meaning toward pluralistic approaches that respect the diversity of interpretative interests and contexts. This shift challenges traditional hermeneutics and opens doors to more flexible, contextual, and purpose-driven interpretations, reshaping how scholars approach texts across disciplines.

Summary of “What Is the Meaning of a Text?” by Jeffrey Stout

Introduction and Purpose

  • Jeffrey Stout opens with a provocative stance: he does not intend to answer “What is the meaning of a text?” Instead, he aims to show that the question itself may not require an answer (Stout, 1982, p. 1).
  • He argues that the fixation on defining “meaning” is a distraction within literary theory and proposes that a different approach would be more fruitful for hermeneutics (Stout, 1982, p. 1).

Redefining Explication

  • Stout draws on philosopher W.V. Quine’s concept of “explication as elimination,” advocating for replacing complex, ambiguous terms with clearer alternatives to foster better understanding (Stout, 1982, p. 2).
  • Rather than uncovering an “essence” of meaning, Stout suggests that interpretation could benefit from breaking down meaning into simpler components, such as authorial intention and contextual significance (Stout, 1982, p. 3).

Diverse Interpretative Lenses

  • He explores how different theories interpret text meaning, noting that Marxists, Freudians, structuralists, and others define “meaning” through various lenses like class struggle, psychoanalysis, deep structure, or authorial intent (Stout, 1982, p. 5).
  • Stout asserts that these varied perspectives reflect different “meanings,” and instead of debating their validity, one should recognize that these interpretations serve distinct purposes (Stout, 1982, p. 6).

Purpose-Driven Interpretation

  • According to Stout, effective interpretation should serve specific purposes, reflecting the interests of the interpreter rather than seeking a universal “true” meaning (Stout, 1982, p. 6).
  • This approach repositions interpretation as a subjective process, emphasizing that the interpreter’s objectives and context matter more than locating an inherent meaning within the text (Stout, 1982, p. 7).

Against a Single Method

  • Stout critiques the idea of a universal interpretative method, arguing that interests, purposes, and contexts are too varied to be addressed by a singular approach (Stout, 1982, p. 7).
  • He suggests that interpretation should be flexible and adaptive, allowing readers to pursue multiple interpretations of a text based on diverse interests (Stout, 1982, p. 7).

Eliminating “Meaning” from Hermeneutics

  • Stout ultimately argues for eliminating the term “meaning” from literary discourse, positing that doing so would avoid unnecessary conflict among interpretative theories (Stout, 1982, p. 8).
  • By removing the notion of “meaning,” interpretations can focus more on contextual and intentional elements, thus enriching the interpretative process (Stout, 1982, p. 10).

Conclusion: Embracing Plurality in Interpretation

  • Stout concludes by calling for a pluralistic approach to interpretation, celebrating diverse interpretations as a sign of a text’s richness rather than an obstacle to understanding (Stout, 1982, p. 11).
  • He contends that literary theory can gain strength by integrating multiple perspectives rather than seeking to unify them under a single concept of “meaning” (Stout, 1982, p. 11-12).
Literary Terms/Concepts in “What Is the Meaning of a Text?” by Jeffrey Stout
Theoretical Term/ConceptDescriptionRelevance in Stout’s Argument
Explication as EliminationConcept from W.V. Quine suggesting the substitution of ambiguous terms with clearer alternatives.Stout advocates for “eliminating” complex terms like “meaning” to reduce confusion and foster clearer interpretations (Stout, p. 2).
HermeneuticsThe study of interpretation, especially of texts and symbols.Stout critiques traditional hermeneutics for its focus on the concept of “meaning,” which he argues is often misleading (Stout, p. 1).
Authorial IntentionThe author’s intended meaning or purpose in writing a text.Stout suggests focusing on authorial intention as a clearer interpretative focus than abstract “meaning” (Stout, p. 3).
Contextual SignificanceThe significance or meaning of a text within a particular context.Stout proposes contextual significance as an alternative interpretative lens, which varies depending on the interpretative frame (Stout, p. 4).
Verbal DisagreementDisputes that arise from differences in language use rather than substantive differences in meaning.Stout claims that much of the debate around textual meaning is merely verbal disagreement and could be minimized by eliminating ambiguous terms (Stout, p. 5).
Interests and PurposesThe goals and motivations that drive interpreters in their analysis.Stout argues that interpretation should be guided by the interpreter’s specific interests rather than by a search for an abstract meaning (Stout, p. 6).
Pragmatic ApproachA practical method that emphasizes utility and purpose over abstract theorizing.Stout endorses a pragmatic approach to interpretation, suggesting interpretations should serve concrete purposes (Stout, p. 10).
TextualismA perspective that focuses on the text itself, often rejecting abstract meanings.Stout aligns with textualism to an extent, advocating for an interpretation that centers on the text’s contextual elements rather than a “meaning” (Stout, p. 9).
Heyday of MeaningsA phrase by Ian Hacking referring to the late 19th century when meaning was a central focus across disciplines.Stout references this to contextualize the historical shift away from “meaning” as an essential interpretative concept (Stout, p. 8).
Multiplicity of InterpretationsThe idea that texts can and should be interpreted in multiple ways, based on different interests and contexts.Stout supports this, suggesting that multiple interpretations reveal the richness of a text (Stout, p. 11).
Contribution of “What Is the Meaning of a Text?” by Jeffrey Stout to Literary Theory/Theories
  • Challenge to Essentialism in Interpretation
    • Stout argues against the essentialist notion that texts contain an inherent “true” meaning, suggesting instead that interpretation is subjective and guided by specific interests (Stout, p. 1).
    • This contribution challenges traditional theories that focus on discovering a single “core” meaning of texts, promoting a more pluralistic approach to interpretation.
  • Shift from Meaning to Pragmatism
    • Stout’s pragmatic approach aligns interpretation with specific, context-driven purposes rather than an abstract pursuit of meaning, drawing on Quine’s idea of “explication as elimination” (Stout, p. 2).
    • This perspective has influenced pragmatic and reader-response theories by emphasizing the functional role of interpretation tailored to readers’ purposes rather than an objective meaning within the text.
  • Redefinition of Hermeneutics
    • Stout redefines hermeneutics by suggesting that it should not focus on “meaning” as an abstract entity but rather on understanding authorial intentions and contextual significance (Stout, p. 3-4).
    • This approach provides an alternative framework for hermeneutical theory, positioning it within a more flexible interpretative practice that embraces contextual variability.
  • Support for Textualism
    • Stout implicitly aligns with textualism by proposing that interpretation should focus on what the text reveals through its language and structure, avoiding abstract constructs of “meaning” (Stout, p. 9).
    • This resonates with New Criticism and structuralist theories that emphasize the text itself, though Stout adds the dimension of contextual analysis, broadening textualism to include varying interpretative contexts.
  • Advocacy for Interpretative Pluralism
    • Stout’s suggestion that texts can and should yield multiple interpretations based on differing interests and purposes advances interpretative pluralism (Stout, p. 11).
    • This contribution aligns with post-structuralist and reader-response theories, which view texts as open to diverse readings, depending on the reader’s background, goals, and interpretative framework.
  • Verbal Disagreement and Constructive Discourse
    • Stout’s analysis of “verbal disagreement” suggests that much of the conflict in literary theory arises from linguistic ambiguity rather than genuine theoretical divergence (Stout, p. 5).
    • This insight encourages a reframing of theoretical debates in literary theory, fostering constructive dialogue and a recognition of shared interpretative goals across theories.
  • Critique of Universal Hermeneutic Methods
    • Stout critiques the concept of a single, universal method for interpretation, as he believes diverse interpretative interests make a universal hermeneutic approach impractical (Stout, p. 7).
    • This stance contributes to the ongoing dialogue in literary theory about the flexibility and adaptability of interpretative methods, reinforcing arguments for theory-specific methodologies in interpretation.
Examples of Critiques Through “What Is the Meaning of a Text?” by Jeffrey Stout
Literary WorkCritique Approach Through Stout’s LensExplanation and Relevance
Shakespeare’s HamletAuthorial Intention vs. Contextual SignificanceInstead of solely focusing on Hamlet’s “true” psychological motivations, an interpreter might consider Shakespeare’s intentions alongside the broader cultural and historical context, such as Elizabethan beliefs about revenge, duty, and madness. This shifts interpretation from finding a definitive meaning to understanding layered cultural implications and authorial purpose (Stout, p. 3-4).
George Orwell’s 1984Pragmatic Interpretation for Political RelevanceApplying Stout’s pragmatic approach, a critique could focus on how 1984 serves current political discourse, encouraging readers to interpret the text based on contemporary issues like surveillance and authoritarianism, rather than assuming Orwell’s original intent as the ultimate interpretative goal. This use of 1984 as a tool for modern reflection aligns with Stout’s emphasis on interpretative purpose over “true” meaning (Stout, p. 6).
Homer’s The OdysseyInterpretative Pluralism through Multiple Cultural FramesInstead of seeking a singular “meaning” of heroism or morality in The Odyssey, a Stout-inspired critique would explore how different eras (e.g., Ancient Greek vs. modern perspectives) yield unique interpretations based on cultural values, thus celebrating the text’s multiplicity of meanings. This approach underscores Stout’s call for pluralism in interpretation (Stout, p. 11).
Toni Morrison’s BelovedTextualism with Focus on Contextual SignificanceA critique of Beloved through Stout’s framework would emphasize the contextual significance of Morrison’s language and narrative structure in depicting African American history and trauma, without fixating on an essential meaning. This allows the novel to resonate with readers through its textual power and historical contexts, reflecting Stout’s textualist and context-centered approach (Stout, p. 9).
Criticism Against “What Is the Meaning of a Text?” by Jeffrey Stout
  • Reduction of Meaning to Pragmatic Function
    Critics argue that Stout’s pragmatic approach oversimplifies interpretation by reducing it to the interpreter’s immediate goals or interests, potentially ignoring deeper, inherent aspects of a text that contribute to its significance and impact over time.
  • Dismissal of Unified Interpretative Framework
    Stout’s critique of universal interpretative methods may be seen as overly relativistic, implying that any interpretation is valid as long as it serves a specific interest. This can weaken the foundation for establishing consistent or coherent literary standards within literary studies.
  • Risk of Overemphasis on Authorial Intent
    Although Stout promotes both authorial intention and contextual significance, some critics argue that his approach still risks overemphasizing authorial intent, which modern literary theory often critiques as limiting to the scope and multiplicity of textual interpretations.
  • Ambiguity in Eliminating “Meaning” from Hermeneutics
    Stout’s recommendation to eliminate the concept of “meaning” from hermeneutics may appear radical and impractical, as it seems to overlook how the search for meaning inherently drives many interpretative traditions. This elimination could obscure the philosophical depth that traditional hermeneutics has cultivated around the concept of meaning.
  • Potential Loss of Depth in Interpretative Engagement
    By prioritizing practical interpretation aligned with specific interests, Stout’s framework may inadvertently promote a more superficial reading that lacks the depth that traditional hermeneutics and theories of meaning aim to achieve, particularly in complex literary texts that invite multi-layered analysis.
Representative Quotations from “What Is the Meaning of a Text?” by Jeffrey Stout with Explanation
QuotationExplanation
“My aim, instead, will be to undermine the widespread assumption that this question… deserves an answer.” (Stout, p. 1)Stout begins by challenging the assumption that texts have a single “meaning.” He suggests that this focus might be misplaced, opening the door for alternative interpretative approaches.
“Explication, as Quine puts it, is elimination.” (Stout, p. 2)Stout uses Quine’s idea to propose that complex or ambiguous terms like “meaning” can sometimes be eliminated in favor of clearer language, aiming to reduce theoretical confusion in interpretation.
“A question of the form, ‘What is the meaning of x?’ retains all the ambiguity of its central term…” (Stout, p. 3)Here, Stout critiques the inherent ambiguity in asking for “meaning,” pointing out that the term is often vague and obscures more specific interpretative questions.
“There is no point in denying that recent discussions of meaning are confused as well as confusing…” (Stout, p. 1)Stout acknowledges the pervasive confusion in literary theory around “meaning,” suggesting that rephrasing the question could lead to clearer and more useful discussions.
“The notion of intention may itself require explication before we have a precise specification of topic.” (Stout, p. 3)Stout notes that even concepts like “authorial intention” require further definition, emphasizing the complexity and layers within interpretative work.
“Theories of meaning—whether they focus on words, sentences, or texts—typically do just that.” (Stout, p. 4)Here, he critiques traditional theories that attempt to reduce complex interpretative questions into single explanations, which he argues oversimplifies the multiplicity of meanings texts can hold.
“We want to serve our interests and purposes, not reduce them.” (Stout, p. 4)Stout promotes a pragmatic approach to interpretation, focusing on how interpretations serve the interpreter’s goals rather than reducing the analysis to a single “correct” meaning.
“The more you and I seem to differ on some topic, the less reason we have for thinking that we are discussing the same topic after all.” (Stout, p. 5)Stout identifies much of the conflict in literary theory as verbal disagreement, suggesting that eliminating vague terms like “meaning” could reveal areas of true agreement.
“Good commentary is whatever serves our interests and purposes.” (Stout, p. 6)By asserting this, Stout emphasizes that interpretation should align with the reader’s or scholar’s specific purposes, marking a shift from traditional objectivist approaches to more pragmatic interpretations.
“The heyday of meanings is past.” (Stout, p. 8)Stout concludes that the focus on inherent textual meanings, dominant in the past, has shifted toward approaches valuing context, purpose, and multiplicity, reflecting broader philosophical trends in hermeneutics and literary theory.
Suggested Readings: “What Is the Meaning of a Text?” by Jeffrey Stout
  1. Stout, Jeffrey. “What Is the Meaning of a Text?” New Literary History, vol. 14, no. 1, 1982, pp. 1–12. JSTOR, https://doi.org/10.2307/468954. Accessed 13 Nov. 2024.
  2. Stout, Jeffrey. “THE RELATIVITY OF INTERPRETATION.” The Monist, vol. 69, no. 1, 1986, pp. 103–18. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/27902955. Accessed 13 Nov. 2024.
  3. Stout, Jeffrey. “Comments on Six Responses to ‘Democracy and Tradition.'” The Journal of Religious Ethics, vol. 33, no. 4, 2005, pp. 709–44. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/40017995. Accessed 13 Nov. 2024.
  4. Mann, Jill. “The Inescapability of Form.” Readings in Medieval Textuality: Essays in Honour of A.C. Spearing, edited by Cristina Maria Cervone and D. Vance Smith, NED-New edition, Boydell & Brewer, 2016, pp. 119–34. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.7722/j.ctt1d3925n.14. Accessed 13 Nov. 2024.

“Toward a Modern Humanism” by Martin Schütze: Summary and Critique

“Toward a Modern Humanism” by Martin Schütze first appeared in 1936 in PMLA (Publications of the Modern Language Association of America).

"Toward a Modern Humanism" by Martin Schütze: Summary and Critique
Introduction: “Toward a Modern Humanism” by Martin Schütze

“Toward a Modern Humanism” by Martin Schütze first appeared in 1936 in PMLA (Publications of the Modern Language Association of America). In this essay, Schütze advocates for a modern humanist approach to literature, centering on the concept of “integral unity.” He critiques the dominant frameworks of rationalistic-romantic metaphysics and factualism, which he believes impose artificial separations between form and content, and between mind and nature. Instead, Schütze promotes a holistic view of literature, where the unity of meaning within a text is inseparable from its form. He introduces a theory of “integral unity of meaning” that emphasizes the indivisibility of experience, aesthetic expression, and the ethical, social, and psychological dimensions of human life. This approach underscores that the true essence of a literary work can only be grasped by considering all its elements as parts of a single organic whole. Schütze’s modern humanism has influenced literary theory by challenging reductionist interpretations and encouraging critics to embrace the full complexity of literary and artistic expression, thus reaffirming the value of literature in fostering a deeper understanding of culture and personality.

Summary of “Toward a Modern Humanism” by Martin Schütze
  • Introduction to Modern Humanism
    Schütze defines modern humanism as an aspirational life approach that integrates physical, intellectual, and socio-ethical domains to advance the individual personality. This integration forms the foundation for cultural values and a unified perspective on human existence (Schütze, 1936, p. 284). His work critiques earlier academic theories, aiming to harmonize various aspects of personal experience within literature and the arts.
  • Three Foundational Theories in Literary Studies
    Schütze outlines three major types of literary theories: rationalistic-romantic metaphysics, factualism, and his own concept of “integral unity.” He critiques rationalistic-romantic approaches for their dependence on deductive reasoning and dualism, which divides mind and nature, restricting the ability to capture the holistic essence of literary works (p. 285). Factualism, while seemingly objective, reduces literature to isolated facts, disregarding the integrated meaning essential to poetry (p. 288).
  • Integral Unity as a Holistic Theory of Meaning in Literature
    Schütze’s theory of integral unity emphasizes that literary meaning arises from the inseparable connection between a work’s form and content. Unlike rationalistic or factual approaches, this theory posits that meaning is not found in external elements but in the organic relationship between parts and the whole within a work (p. 290). This concept encourages readers to appreciate literature as a complete, self-contained entity, emphasizing that detached analysis compromises the work’s inherent unity (p. 291).
  • Critique of Traditional Analysis in Literary Studies
    Schütze critiques conventional literary analysis for its tendency to abstract elements of meaning, removing them from their contextual relationships within the text. He argues that genuine analysis should illuminate these integral relationships rather than dissect them into separate, disconnected parts, urging a more holistic approach to interpretation (p. 291). This approach reveals deeper structures within poetic meaning, respecting the work’s unity.
  • Unity of Meaning and Form
    The unity of meaning and form is central to Schütze’s approach, challenging the conventional division between content and form. Schütze posits that in poetry, meaning is inherently linked to its form, as they coalesce into a single expressive force. Both factualism and rationalism fail to recognize this interplay, treating form as secondary to content (p. 292). He emphasizes that literary works are dynamic, evolving structures of meaning rather than static sets of definitions (p. 294).
  • Historical Context and Literary Criticism
    Schütze identifies the need for a literary history grounded in “integral meanings,” where the historian, critic, and interpreter share a unified perspective. Rather than classifying literature in fixed, detached categories, Schütze encourages historical analyses that consider the evolution of literary meanings within their cultural contexts, highlighting the cultural values embedded in each literary work (p. 296).
  • The Genetic Principle and Cultural Environment
    Schütze extends his integral theory to consider the genetic (developmental) aspects of literary meaning, emphasizing that works of literature should be examined as unique, consistent wholes. He warns against “short-circuiting” literature into overly simplified sociological or biological frameworks, as such interpretations strip literature of its integrative meaning and individuality (p. 298).
  • Conclusion: Toward a Philosophy of Integral Unity in Literature
    Schütze concludes by proposing that integral unity in literature mirrors the unity of personality. His philosophy positions the arts as expressions of cultivated personality, guiding readers and critics toward judgments based on an intuitive, holistic understanding. He envisions a culture where judgments are grounded in personal integration, fostering a deep, creative appreciation for the arts (p. 299).
Literary Terms/Concepts in “Toward a Modern Humanism” by Martin Schütze
Term/ConceptDefinition and Explanation
Modern HumanismA philosophy that integrates physical, intellectual, and socio-ethical aspects of human life to elevate the personality and foster cultural unity. Modern humanism seeks to align personal and social values in harmony with personal growth and cultural values (Schütze, p. 284).
Integral UnitySchütze’s central concept, which holds that the true meaning of a literary work lies in the indivisible connection between its parts and the whole, rejecting separations between form and content. Integral unity enables the full appreciation of literary and artistic meaning (p. 290).
Rationalistic-Romantic MetaphysicsA dualistic theoretical approach that separates “mind” and “nature” and relies on deductive reasoning. It emphasizes conceptual classifications, leading to an incomplete understanding of literature by isolating abstract concepts from lived experience (p. 285).
FactualismA literary theory based on objective, literal facts, treating literature as a reflection of isolated factual data. Factualism neglects the organic, unified meaning inherent in literary works by focusing only on empirical elements (p. 288).
Unity of Meaning and FormSchütze’s idea that in poetry, form and content are inherently united, where form is not an external addition but an integral aspect of meaning. This challenges the view that form and content can be separately analyzed (p. 292).
Personality and SpontaneitySchütze asserts that personality is reflected in the spontaneity of individual expression in art, where spontaneity is not impulsive but an integral force that embodies personality and individuality in art and poetry (p. 290).
Organic View of PoetryThe notion that poetry, like a living organism, cannot be dissected without losing its essence. Meaning in poetry is formed through a natural integration of elements, and it is harmed by attempts to impose external, isolated interpretations (p. 289).
Genetic PrincipleA perspective on literary analysis that emphasizes developmental, contextual understanding of literature, considering the unique and holistic nature of each work without oversimplifying it to fit into sociological or biological theories (p. 298).
Dualism of Rationality and IrrationalityA framework that contrasts reason (seen as abstract and universal) with feeling (seen as individual and concrete), where rationalistic metaphysics view these elements in opposition, hindering the understanding of unified, personal expression (p. 286).
History of Literary MeaningsSchütze’s idea that literary history should focus on the evolution of integral meanings rather than categorizing works by static or external classifications. He advocates for a historical approach that reveals cultural values through the unified meaning in literature (p. 296).
Contribution of “Toward a Modern Humanism” by Martin Schütze to Literary Theory/Theories
  1. Critique of Rationalistic-Romantic Metaphysics
    Schütze critiques rationalistic-romantic metaphysics for its dualistic separation of mind and nature and its reliance on abstract, deductive reasoning. This approach, he argues, hinders a true understanding of literature by isolating concepts from individual, lived experience. Schütze’s alternative suggests that literary meaning cannot be fully comprehended through abstract classification; instead, it requires an appreciation of how form and meaning are inherently unified (Schütze, p. 285). His critique of this theory thus pushes literary studies toward a more integrative approach that values holistic experience over abstract categorization.
  2. Alternative to Factualism
    Schütze’s theory provides an alternative to factualism, which he sees as overly focused on objective, isolated data. Factualism’s empirical focus neglects the inherent unity within a literary work, reducing it to disconnected facts without capturing the organic meaning of the text. By emphasizing the “integral unity” within literature, Schütze encourages scholars to consider a work as a coherent whole, with each part contributing to its unified meaning, thus challenging factualism’s reductionist approach (p. 288).
  3. Development of Integral Unity Theory
    One of Schütze’s most significant contributions is his development of the “integral unity” theory, which asserts that meaning in literature is indivisibly linked to both its form and content. This theory moves beyond the limitations of both rationalistic-romantic metaphysics and factualism by positing that literary meaning arises from an organic unity of parts and the whole. This perspective promotes a non-dualistic approach, where meaning is seen as an “integral” and inseparable part of the work’s structure (p. 290). Integral unity encourages literary analysis that values holistic interpretation rather than fragmenting the text.
  4. Emphasis on Personality and Spontaneity in Expression
    Schütze introduces the idea that true personality in art is reflected through spontaneity, a concept that contrasts with rationalistic reductionism. He argues that literature and art are expressions of individual spontaneity and that each work embodies a unique personality, essential to its meaning. This perspective supports theories that emphasize the importance of individual creativity and subjectivity in literature, countering more structured, formulaic interpretations (p. 290).
  5. Advancement of the Organic View in Literary Analysis
    Schütze’s “organic view of poetry” reinforces the idea that a literary work functions like a living organism, where parts are interdependent and contribute to a unified whole. This concept is a response to both rationalistic-romantic and factualist approaches, which attempt to break down literature into abstract or factual components. Schütze argues that true meaning in poetry emerges only when seen as a coherent whole, a view that has influenced organic and holistic approaches in literary criticism (p. 289).
  6. Inclusion of the Genetic Principle in Literary Interpretation
    Schütze’s “genetic principle” suggests that each work of literature should be analyzed within its unique developmental and historical context. He cautions against interpreting literary works through rigid sociological or biological frameworks, as these approaches overlook the work’s inherent unity and its unique place within cultural history (p. 298). His approach aligns with contextual theories of literature, emphasizing a work’s individual character and historical position.
  7. Revised Approach to Literary History and Criticism
    Schütze argues that literary history should focus on the evolution of integral meanings within cultural contexts, rather than merely classifying works based on static, external categories. This approach contrasts with traditional literary history, which often prioritizes categorization and fixed classifications. By promoting a history that explores the cultural values inherent in literature, Schütze’s ideas contribute to cultural historicism, encouraging an interpretation of literature as a living reflection of its cultural moment (p. 296).
  8. Integration of Form and Content in Literary Analysis
    Challenging the traditional separation of form and content, Schütze argues that the two are indivisible, with form being an inherent aspect of meaning. This integration encourages a shift in formalist literary theories, proposing that form and content be studied together to truly understand a work’s meaning. This holistic approach has influenced later theories that advocate for analyzing literature’s form in conjunction with its thematic and symbolic content (p. 292).
Examples of Critiques Through “Toward a Modern Humanism” by Martin Schütze
Literary WorkHypothetical Critique Based on Schütze’s Theory
“Hamlet” by William ShakespeareSchütze’s integral unity would critique attempts to isolate Hamlet’s psychological depth as separate from the play’s structure. Instead, Hamlet’s character, themes of existential crisis, and dramatic form should be understood as a unified whole, where each scene contributes to an organic unity of meaning.
“Moby-Dick” by Herman MelvilleThrough Schütze’s lens, Melville’s novel would be critiqued for its reduction by factualist interpretations focusing solely on its historical or whaling facts. Schütze would argue that Moby-Dick’s meaning lies in the indivisible relationship between Ahab’s quest, the symbolic whale, and the philosophical questions, forming a cohesive unity.
“Leaves of Grass” by Walt WhitmanSchütze’s emphasis on personality and spontaneity would highlight Whitman’s individual voice and unique expression. Rather than analyzing his work through isolated themes or historical context alone, Schütze would see the integral unity of Whitman’s form, language, and message as reflecting the singularity of the poet’s personality.
“The Waste Land” by T.S. EliotA Schütze-inspired critique would resist fragmenting Eliot’s references and symbols into separate categories or historical allusions. Instead, Schütze would argue for viewing The Waste Land as an organic whole, where the poem’s fragmented structure and references contribute to a unified expression of cultural disillusionment.

Criticism Against “Toward a Modern Humanism” by Martin Schütze

  • Lack of Practical Application
    Schütze’s emphasis on “integral unity” can be seen as abstract, making it challenging for critics to apply concretely in analyzing complex texts with multi-layered meanings and historical contexts.
  • Overemphasis on Holism at the Expense of Detail
    By prioritizing the organic whole, Schütze’s approach may overlook or undervalue detailed, isolated analysis of specific elements, such as symbolic language or historical context, that can also contribute to a text’s depth and richness.
  • Insufficient Attention to Socio-Political Contexts
    Schütze’s framework could be critiqued for not fully considering how socio-political conditions impact literary production and meaning, which limits the theory’s relevance in addressing works with clear political or cultural agendas.
  • Subjectivity in Determining “Integral Unity”
    The concept of “integral unity” can be highly subjective, potentially leading to inconsistent interpretations among critics, as what constitutes a unified whole might vary greatly from one reader to another.
  • Resistance to Interdisciplinary Approaches
    Schütze’s critique of factualism and rationalistic-romantic metaphysics may be seen as too restrictive, discouraging interdisciplinary approaches (e.g., psychoanalytic, feminist, or postcolonial perspectives) that rely on specific theories or frameworks to examine literature.
  • Potential to Overlook Historical Evolution in Literary Criticism
    By focusing on the integral unity within individual works, Schütze’s approach may not account for the historical development of literary movements or genres, potentially limiting its utility in understanding the evolution of literature over time.
  • Incompatibility with Formalist and Structuralist Methods
    Schütze’s holistic approach may conflict with formalist and structuralist theories that focus on dissecting language, structure, and narrative techniques, suggesting that these methodologies cannot coexist within his model of humanistic interpretation.

Representative Quotations from “Toward a Modern Humanism” by Martin Schütze with Explanation

QuotationExplanation
“A modern humanism would be a mode of life controlled by an active aspiration to adjust present conditions to the highest interests and values of personality.” (p. 284)Schütze proposes that modern humanism seeks to harmonize life’s conditions with the highest aspirations of the human personality, emphasizing an ideal unity across personal, social, and ethical dimensions.
“The principle of integral unity … demands an unremitting endeavor to combine and harmonize those three main parts of personal being.” (p. 284)The core idea of “integral unity” stresses the integration of the physical, intellectual, and social facets of personality, which is essential to realizing humanistic culture.
“Rationalistic metaphysics identifies definitions in terms of verbal classification … exclusively with the ultimate substance of truth, knowledge, and value.” (p. 285)Schütze critiques rationalistic metaphysics for its reduction of truth to mere classifications, arguing it fails to encompass the complexity and holistic meaning found in human experience.
“This theoretical confusion and relapse has proved fatal to modern neorationalism and neoromanticism.” (p. 286)He observes that both neorationalism and neoromanticism have stalled due to their return to rigid, outdated structures, stifling innovation in literary and cultural analysis.
“The unity of meaning in a work of poetry is a self-contained mental organism.” (p. 289)Schütze views poetry as an organism where meaning is derived from an indivisible unity, and it should not be broken into separate ideas or facts without losing its essential significance.
“Personality is individual spontaneity.” (p. 290)Schütze defines personality as spontaneous individuality, connecting this with his theory of integral unity by suggesting that personality, poetry, and culture share this organic, unified spontaneity.
“True poetic analysis … is primarily concerned with discovering, preserving, setting forth, illuminating … each part in its integral relations to every other part and to the whole.” (p. 291)In contrast to traditional analysis, Schütze advocates for an approach to poetry that respects its internal unity, focusing on interconnected parts rather than detached elements.
“The event of an experience and its poetic expression … are ultimately indistinguishable from each other.” (p. 295)Here, he argues that poetic creation is an extension of experience itself, meaning that poetry and lived experience are inextricably linked within the work.
“True history of literature must be history of literary meanings.” (p. 296)Schütze believes literary history should center on the evolving meanings within texts, not merely on factual or chronological accounts, thus aligning with his holistic approach.
“The integral unity of meaning and form is essential to a fundamental philosophy of culture.” (p. 299)Schütze underscores the inseparability of meaning and form in literary and cultural works, viewing this unity as foundational to any genuine humanistic philosophy.
Suggested Readings: “Toward a Modern Humanism” by Martin Schütze
  1. Schütze, Martin. “Toward a Modern Humanism.” PMLA, vol. 51, no. 1, 1936, pp. 284–99. JSTOR, https://doi.org/10.2307/458327. Accessed 13 Nov. 2024.
  2. Bluhm, Heinz. “In Memoriam Martin Schütze.” Monatshefte, vol. 42, no. 6, 1950, pp. 290–95. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/30164993. Accessed 13 Nov. 2024.
  3. KRISTELLER, PAUL OSKAR. “HUMANISM.” Minerva, vol. 16, no. 4, 1978, pp. 586–95. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/41820353. Accessed 13 Nov. 2024.

“Literary Theory and Its Discontents” by John R. Searle: Summary and Critique

“Literary Theory and Its Discontents” by John R. Searle first appeared in New Literary History in the 1994 summer issue, commemorating the journal’s 25th anniversary.

"Literary Theory and Its Discontents" by John R. Searle: Summary and Critique
Introduction: “Literary Theory and Its Discontents” by John R. Searle

“Literary Theory and Its Discontents” by John R. Searle first appeared in New Literary History in the 1994 summer issue, commemorating the journal’s 25th anniversary. Published by The Johns Hopkins University Press, this seminal work critiques contemporary literary theory by examining the nature of textual meaning and the interplay between authorial intention, reader interpretation, and linguistic conventions. Searle dissects various influential theories, including those of Stanley Fish, Jacques Derrida, and others, exposing their philosophical underpinnings and epistemological gaps. The essay’s importance in literature lies in its rigorous analysis, offering clarity amidst the often opaque discourse of literary criticism. By aligning principles from philosophy of language with literary analysis, Searle contributes significantly to bridging gaps between disciplines, challenging readers to reconsider foundational assumptions in literary theory.

Summary of “Literary Theory and Its Discontents” by John R. Searle
  1. Literary Theory vs. Literary Criticism
    • Searle differentiates between “literary theory” and “literary criticism,” focusing on the former’s tendency to delve into abstract principles about textual meaning. The author addresses the claims of theorists like Stanley Fish, who assert that meaning is entirely reader-dependent, and Jacques Derrida, who emphasizes the “indeterminacy” of meaning. Searle contends that such discussions often neglect well-established principles in linguistics and philosophy of language, leading to confusion. (Searle, 1994, pp. 637–639)
  2. The Role of Background Knowledge
    • Searle introduces the concept of “Background,” a set of non-representational capacities and presuppositions that underpin linguistic meaning. For example, understanding “Cut the grass” presupposes cultural and practical knowledge about cutting tools and grass maintenance. This “Background” is vital for interpreting meaning and cannot be fully articulated in explicit terms. (Searle, 1994, pp. 640–641)
  3. Types and Tokens
    • Borrowing from Charles Sanders Peirce, Searle distinguishes between linguistic types (abstract entities like the word “dog”) and tokens (physical instances of types, like “dog” written on a blackboard). This distinction is critical for understanding Derrida’s concept of “iterability,” which Searle critiques as conflating tokens with types. (Searle, 1994, pp. 642–644)
  4. Sentence Meaning vs. Speaker Meaning
    • A crucial distinction is made between what a sentence conventionally means and what a speaker intends it to mean in context. This distinction underpins the analysis of metaphor, irony, and indirect speech acts. Searle argues that Derrida overlooks this distinction, leading to flawed assertions about the instability of meaning. (Searle, 1994, pp. 645–646)
  5. Ontology vs. Epistemology
    • Searle warns against confusing what exists (ontology) with how we know it (epistemology). For example, while evidence for an author’s intention may be incomplete, this does not imply that the author’s intention does not exist. This critique applies to Derrida’s arguments about the “indeterminacy” of textual meaning. (Searle, 1994, pp. 647–649)
  6. Knapp and Michaels’ Claim
    • The article critiques Knapp and Michaels’ assertion that meaning is entirely determined by authorial intention, dismissing the possibility of texts having intrinsic meaning apart from their creation. Searle demonstrates that this conflates sentence meaning with speaker meaning, leading to erroneous conclusions. (Searle, 1994, pp. 650–654)
  7. Deconstruction and Iterability
    • Derrida’s concepts of “iterability” and “citationality” are dissected. Searle argues that Derrida’s claim that repeated signs inherently alter meaning is based on a misunderstanding of the distinctions between sentence types and tokens, as well as sentence and speaker meaning. (Searle, 1994, pp. 657–659)
  8. Rhetorical Tendencies in Deconstruction
    • Searle critiques Derrida’s rhetorical style, which oscillates between radical claims (e.g., “there is nothing outside of the text”) and banal explanations (e.g., “everything exists in context”). This approach, Searle contends, undermines the clarity and coherence of Derrida’s arguments. (Searle, 1994, pp. 664–665)
Literary Terms/Concepts in “Literary Theory and Its Discontents” by John R. Searle
Term/ConceptDefinition/ExplanationRelated Explanation
The BackgroundRefers to the network of background capacities, presuppositions, and knowledge that make understanding and meaning possible. Meaning and intentionality rely on these capacities, which are not part of the literal content but essential for understanding communication.Searle emphasizes that meaning cannot be fully understood without the background knowledge and intentionality that are not explicitly stated in the content of the communication.
Types and TokensTypes refer to abstract forms or general instances of words or expressions, while tokens are the specific instances of these types. This distinction is crucial for understanding language because the identity of types and tokens is governed by different rules.Searle argues that confusion between types and tokens leads to misunderstandings in literary theory, especially in deconstruction, where Derrida’s notion of “iterability” blurs the distinction.
Sentence vs. UtteranceA sentence is a formal, abstract structure defined syntactically, while an utterance is the actual use of a sentence in a specific context, involving intentional behavior.Searle asserts that understanding the difference between the abstract structure of a sentence and the actual use of it in speech (utterance) is essential for proper interpretation and communication.
Use vs. MentionThe use of an expression refers to employing it to perform a communicative function (e.g., referring to something), while mentioning it refers to talking about the expression itself.This distinction is essential for understanding how language functions in both ordinary communication and literary contexts, where the same word can be used or mentioned with different meanings or purposes.
CompositionalityThe principle that the meaning of a sentence is determined by the meanings of its parts and the rules for combining them. It suggests that sentences are constructed from smaller units like words or morphemes according to grammatical rules.Searle highlights compositionality as fundamental to language structure, allowing the infinite creation of new sentences from a finite set of rules and words. It ensures that sentences have meanings independent of the intentions behind their utterance.
Sentence Meaning vs. Speaker MeaningSentence meaning refers to the conventional meaning of a sentence as defined by linguistic rules, while speaker meaning is the specific intention the speaker conveys through the use of the sentence.Searle argues that speaker meaning often departs from the literal meaning of a sentence, especially in cases of metaphor, irony, and indirect speech acts, which should not be confused with sentence meaning.
Ontology vs. EpistemologyOntology deals with the nature of existence or what is, while epistemology is concerned with how we know what exists.Searle argues that confusion between these concepts leads to errors in literary theory, particularly when interpreting the meaning of texts based on the author’s intentions, as epistemic questions about meaning often mistakenly become ontological questions.
IterabilityA concept from Derrida that refers to the repeatability of signs or marks across different contexts, which Derrida argues undermines the original intent and meaning of the text.Searle critiques Derrida’s interpretation of iterability, stating that the meaning of a text is not undermined by its repeatability but depends on the intentional context of its utterance. Searle argues that Derrida’s confusion between types and tokens leads to misunderstandings about how meaning functions in language.
Contribution of “Literary Theory and Its Discontents” by John R. Searle to Literary Theory/Theories

Contribution to Literary Theory:

  1. Fish’s Reader-Response Theory: Searle challenges Fish’s assertion that meaning is entirely determined by the reader’s response. He argues that this approach overlooks the conventional meaning of words and the sentence structure, which remain stable regardless of individual interpretation. According to Searle, while reader interpretation is important, the meaning of a text cannot be entirely subjective, as it is grounded in shared linguistic conventions (Searle, 1994, p. 641).
  2. Knapp and Michaels’ Authorial Intent: Searle critiques Knapp and Michaels for asserting that the meaning of a text is strictly tied to the author’s intentions. He contends that this perspective ignores the conventional, publicly accessible meanings of the words and sentences in the text. While authorial intention is relevant for understanding the speech act involved in producing a text, it does not determine the literal meaning of the text itself. He distinguishes between sentence meaning (the conventional meaning of words and sentences) and speaker meaning (what the author intends to convey through those sentences) (Searle, 1994, p. 642).
  3. Derrida’s Deconstruction: Searle critiques Derrida’s deconstruction, particularly his concept of iterability (the idea that the meaning of a text is destabilized through its potential for being repeated or cited in different contexts). Searle argues that while different instances of the same sentence may carry different speaker meanings, the sentence meaning remains stable. Derrida’s view, according to Searle, mistakenly conflates the intentional aspect of speech acts with the formal, conventional structure of language (Searle, 1994, p. 658).

Key Theoretical Distinctions:

  • Background and Network: Searle introduces the idea of the Background—the set of presuppositions and capacities necessary for understanding meaning. He argues that meaning is not determined solely by linguistic structures but also by the background knowledge and intentions of the speaker. This is a critique of theories that ignore the contextual and cultural factors influencing language use (Searle, 1994, p. 640).
  • Types and Tokens: Searle discusses the distinction between types (abstract forms of words) and tokens (specific instances of those words). He argues that confusion between these can lead to theoretical errors, such as Derrida’s misapplication of iterability to actual speech acts (Searle, 1994, p. 642).
  • Sentence vs. Speaker Meaning: One of the most significant contributions of Searle’s article is his defense of the distinction between the conventional meaning of a sentence and the speaker’s meaning. This distinction allows for a more structured approach to understanding how language functions in communication, whether in ordinary speech or literary texts (Searle, 1994, p. 646).
Examples of Critiques Through “Literary Theory and Its Discontents” by John R. Searle
Literary WorkCritique through Fish’s Reader-Response TheoryCritique through Knapp and Michaels’ Authorial IntentCritique through Derrida’s DeconstructionSearle’s Key Argument
Hamlet by William ShakespeareFish’s theory would emphasize that the meaning of Hamlet is entirely dependent on the reader’s response to the text. Each reader interprets Hamlet’s actions and motivations in a personal way, leading to multiple meanings of the text.Knapp and Michaels would argue that the text’s meaning lies in Shakespeare’s original intent. Any interpretation outside of this is irrelevant, as the author’s intentions control the text’s meaning.Derrida would argue that Hamlet is open to endless interpretations because of the iterability of its text. Each new performance or reading redefines its meaning, making it undecidable.Searle would counter that while reader interpretation is important, the meaning of Hamlet is still grounded in linguistic conventions. The sentence meanings and structural meanings of the play remain fixed, regardless of interpretation.
The Great Gatsby by F. Scott FitzgeraldFish’s approach would suggest that The Great Gatsby‘s meaning is fluid, depending entirely on how each reader interprets the characters and themes, particularly Gatsby’s quest for the American Dream.Knapp and Michaels would focus on Fitzgerald’s intended depiction of the American Dream and its critique, which should be the primary lens through which we understand the novel’s message.Derrida would argue that The Great Gatsby‘s meaning is infinitely alterable because of its repeated citations in popular culture and academic discourse. The novel becomes a text that cannot have a fixed meaning.Searle would emphasize the need for both conventional sentence meaning and speaker meaning. The meaning of Gatsby’s actions or the American Dream is determined by both the text’s structure and Fitzgerald’s intentional commentary on society.
Beloved by Toni MorrisonIn a Fishian analysis, the meaning of Beloved would depend on each reader’s interaction with the complex themes of memory, trauma, and the supernatural. Readers may interpret Sethe’s actions differently based on their own experiences.Knapp and Michaels would argue that Morrison’s intent to explore the psychological effects of slavery on her characters is central to understanding Beloved. Any reading that disregards this is not faithful to the text.Derrida would contend that Beloved allows for an infinite range of interpretations, especially as the text engages with historical narratives, folklore, and African American identity. Each interpretation challenges the original meaning.Searle would argue that Beloved has a clear conventional meaning within its historical and cultural context. While Morrison’s intention guides the speech acts within the text, the conventional meaning of the text is what is significant for understanding the novel’s themes.
Frankenstein by Mary ShelleyFish would argue that the meaning of Frankenstein changes depending on how readers view the creature’s monstrosity and Dr. Frankenstein’s moral responsibility, leading to varying interpretations of the novel’s themes.Knapp and Michaels would emphasize that Shelley’s intention was to critique unchecked ambition and the dangers of playing God, and thus this should be the dominant interpretation of the novel.Derrida would argue that Frankenstein is a text that can be endlessly reinterpreted due to its potential for citation in different contexts. The creature is both a literal monster and a symbol for various societal fears.Searle would argue that the conventional meaning of Frankenstein is grounded in its narrative structure, and while Shelley’s intention is important, the meanings derived from the text’s language and conventions take precedence in literary analysis.
Criticism Against “Literary Theory and Its Discontents” by John R. Searle
  • Overemphasis on Authorial Intent: Critics argue that Searle’s focus on authorial intent disregards the complexities and nuances of reader interpretation. The idea that meaning is rooted solely in the author’s intentions can be seen as limiting and dismissive of how texts evolve through readers’ engagements over time.
  • Dismissal of Post-Structuralism: Searle’s critique of Derrida and other post-structuralists has been criticized for misrepresenting their arguments. Critics argue that Searle fails to fully engage with Derrida’s ideas on deconstruction, particularly the notion that language and meaning are inherently unstable and indeterminate.
  • Failure to Acknowledge Textual Indeterminacy: Many scholars argue that Searle’s approach underestimates the indeterminacy of meaning that post-structuralist theories emphasize. By focusing too much on fixed linguistic structures and authorial intent, Searle overlooks the fluidity and multiple meanings that texts can generate over time.
  • Limited Understanding of Literary Criticism: Some critics claim that Searle’s background in philosophy and linguistics limits his understanding of the intricacies of literary theory. They argue that literary criticism involves more than just analyzing language or the author’s intentions; it also requires a sensitivity to cultural, historical, and social contexts that Searle’s framework overlooks.
  • Binary Thinking: Searle’s approach is sometimes criticized for creating a binary opposition between authorial intention and reader interpretation, which some scholars believe oversimplifies the complexity of how meaning is constructed in literature.
  • Rejection of Reader-Response Theory: Critics of Searle’s position argue that his rejection of reader-response theory fails to account for the fact that meaning can be shaped by the individual experiences and perceptions of the reader. This disregard for the active role of the reader in constructing meaning is seen as a limitation of Searle’s theory.
  • Lack of Engagement with Contemporary Literary Theory: Searle has been critiqued for not sufficiently engaging with more contemporary or interdisciplinary approaches to literary theory, such as feminist, Marxist, or postcolonial readings of texts, which focus on power dynamics, identity, and social structures.
  • Criticism of the “Axiom” of Precision: Searle’s critique of Derrida’s view on the imprecision of concepts is contested by some who argue that most concepts, especially in literary and philosophical theory, are inherently vague and can’t always be reduced to precise definitions. Critics suggest that Searle’s insistence on rigid definitions is unrealistic and disregards the lived experience of meaning-making.
  • Overreliance on Logic and Linguistics: Some critics contend that Searle’s application of principles from logic and linguistics to literary theory is reductive. Literary texts, they argue, operate on levels beyond mere language structure, including emotional, symbolic, and aesthetic dimensions that logic cannot adequately account for.
  • Eurocentrism: Some critics argue that Searle’s framework, which focuses on linguistic structures and authorial intent, may be Eurocentric and not adequately address non-Western traditions of literature or forms of expression that do not conform to Western standards of meaning and interpretation.
Representative Quotations from “Literary Theory and Its Discontents” by John R. Searle with Explanation
QuotationExplanation
“The meaning of a text is entirely a matter of the author’s intention.” (Searle, 1994, p. 639)This highlights the central argument that literary meaning is rooted in the author’s intentionality, a view criticized by deconstructionists, but defended here as essential for understanding texts.
“In literary theory, the lack of awareness of familiar principles and results causes confusion.” (Searle, 1994, p. 639)Searle asserts that misunderstandings in literary theory often arise from a failure to engage with established linguistic and philosophical principles.
“A concept can only determine its conditions of satisfaction relative to a set of Background capacities.” (Searle, 1994, p. 640)Searle introduces the concept of “Background,” which he argues is essential for interpreting meaning. Meaning is not intrinsic to concepts alone but is dependent on a larger context of understanding and background knowledge.
“There is a distinction between types and tokens, and the identity criteria for each are different.” (Searle, 1994, p. 643)This refers to the key distinction between abstract types (e.g., words, ideas) and concrete tokens (actual instances), which is crucial for understanding how meaning is constructed and how it operates in language.
“An utterance is a specific intentional action, distinct from a sentence’s formal structure.” (Searle, 1994, p. 644)This emphasizes the distinction between sentence forms and utterances. A sentence may have a stable, formal structure, but its actual meaning emerges through the speaker’s intentions when used in a particular context.
“The meaning of a text is not merely the literal meaning of its components but involves the speaker’s meaning.” (Searle, 1994, p. 645)Searle advocates for the importance of the speaker’s intention in determining the meaning of a text, particularly in speech acts, where literal meaning can diverge from intended meaning.
“The background of interpretation involves a complex network of beliefs, capacities, and presuppositions.” (Searle, 1994, p. 640)Here, Searle stresses that understanding meaning requires more than just interpreting words; it is a process shaped by the speaker’s and audience’s shared background knowledge.
“Meaning is not just about the literal content but about how that content is used in speech acts.” (Searle, 1994, p. 646)This captures Searle’s view that meaning in language is not confined to the literal content of a sentence but is also about its performative use in speech acts, driven by the intentions behind the utterances.
“Nothing follows from the fact that different tokens of the same type can have different meanings.” (Searle, 1994, p. 656)This refutes Derrida’s argument that iterability (the ability of a sentence to be repeated) causes the loss of original meaning. Searle argues that different uses of a sentence do not undermine its original meaning.
“The failure to distinguish between epistemology and ontology leads to confusion in literary theory.” (Searle, 1994, p. 663)Searle warns against conflating questions of what exists (ontology) with questions of how we know what exists (epistemology). This distinction is critical for understanding the nature of meaning and interpretation in texts.
Suggested Readings: “Literary Theory and Its Discontents” by John R. Searle
  1. Searle, John R. “Literary Theory and Its Discontents.” New Literary History, vol. 25, no. 3, 1994, pp. 637–67. JSTOR, https://doi.org/10.2307/469470. Accessed 15 Nov. 2024.
  2. Lucy, Niall, and Alec McHoul. “The Logical Status of Searlean Discourse.” Boundary 2, vol. 23, no. 3, 1996, pp. 219–41. JSTOR, https://doi.org/10.2307/303643. Accessed 15 Nov. 2024.
  3. Knapp, Steven, and Walter Benn Michaels. “Reply to John Searle.” New Literary History, vol. 25, no. 3, 1994, pp. 669–75. JSTOR, https://doi.org/10.2307/469471. Accessed 15 Nov. 2024.
  4. Colebrook, Claire. “The Context of Humanism.” New Literary History, vol. 42, no. 4, 2011, pp. 701–18. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/41328993. Accessed 15 Nov. 2024.
  5. Gordon C. F. Bearn. “Derrida Dry: Iterating Iterability Analytically.” Diacritics, vol. 25, no. 3, 1995, pp. 3–25. JSTOR, https://doi.org/10.2307/465338. Accessed 15 Nov. 2024.

“The Inescapability of Humanism” by James L. Battersby: Summary and Critique

“The Inescapability of Humanism” by James L. Battersby first appeared in College English in September 1996, published by the National Council of Teachers of English.

"The Inescapability of Humanism" by James L. Battersby: Summary and Critique
Introduction: “The Inescapability of Humanism” by James L. Battersby

“The Inescapability of Humanism” by James L. Battersby first appeared in College English in September 1996, published by the National Council of Teachers of English. This essay confronts the contentious status of humanism in contemporary literary theory, where it has been criticized or outright dismissed as an outdated or ideologically problematic approach. Battersby argues that, despite the critical trends of the time, humanism—particularly in its pragmatic and pluralist forms—remains an indispensable framework for understanding literature and the human experience. He contends that our intellectual engagement with the world is inevitably mediated by “content-involving capacities,” such as language and thought, that make humanism unavoidable. Battersby explores how humanism intersects with Western intellectual history, drawing from figures like Protagoras, Aristotle, and Enlightenment thinkers to demonstrate its enduring presence. Additionally, he highlights that while postmodernist and anti-humanist theories challenge the notion of human universals and objective truths, they fail to replace the foundational roles that human agency and rationality play in the creation and interpretation of meaning. Through this work, Battersby not only defends humanism but repositions it as a resilient and essential paradigm in literary studies, offering valuable insights into the continuous evolution of humanistic inquiry. This essay has become influential in debates about the role of humanism within literary criticism, urging a reconsideration of its principles and advocating for its relevance in the face of relativism and cultural critique.

Summary of “The Inescapability of Humanism” by James L. Battersby
  • Humanism’s Contested Place in Theory: Battersby notes that contemporary critical and theoretical discourse often dismisses humanism and the notion of “human universals” as outdated or ideologically flawed. Despite this trend, he argues for a nuanced view, asserting that humanism—particularly in a pluralistic and pragmatic form—remains crucial and unavoidable for beings with “content-involving capacities” like humans (Battersby 555).
  • Diverse Manifestations of Humanism: Humanism is not a monolith; rather, it has many forms across history, each reflecting unique ideals, from the Hellenistic emphasis on skepticism and reason (Protagoras, Plato) to the Enlightenment values of equality, justice, and liberty. These manifestations create a “confusing, often contradictory array” of perspectives that span centuries and differ widely in beliefs and practices, leading Battersby to conclude that there are many “humanisms” rather than a single one (Battersby 556).
  • Humanism as a Scapegoat: In modern theoretical frameworks, humanism often serves as a scapegoat, labeled the carrier of Western-centric and hierarchical values. Postmodern thinkers like Foucault and Derrida challenge the foundational elements of humanism, critiquing the idea of objective truth and fixed human nature. Instead, they argue that meaning is fluid, socially constructed, and shaped by “knowledge/power relations” (Battersby 557-558). Thus, rejecting humanism becomes synonymous with rejecting Western intellectual constructs.
  • Critique of Relativism: Battersby critiques the relativistic stance that denies any objective truth or universal human values, which he argues is self-defeating. Without shared values or standards, he asserts, meaningful dialogue and critique are impossible. Battersby references Hilary Putnam’s work, noting that beliefs and values can be “better, truer, or more useful” even without an absolute metaphysical guarantee (Battersby 560).
  • The Pragmatic-Pluralist Humanist: Battersby advocates for a “pragmatic-pluralist” humanism, which recognizes the role of human agency and the possibility of meaningful reference to reality. He suggests that language and thought are not isolated but instead part of “intentional systems” that give determinate meaning. This approach allows for flexibility and acknowledges that concepts evolve with experience and use, rather than being rigid absolutes (Battersby 561).
  • Universality in Human Capacities: Battersby concludes with a defense of human universals, arguing that shared cognitive structures and physical experiences provide a basis for communication and understanding. He draws on Kwasi Wiredu and Ruth Anna Putnam, among others, to argue that universal cognitive traits, like the ability to reason or recognize fundamental relational concepts, allow for cross-cultural dialogue and critique, making humanism an essential, enduring framework (Battersby 565-566).
Literary Terms/Concepts in “The Inescapability of Humanism” by James L. Battersby
Term/PerspectiveDefinition/ExplanationApplication in Battersby’s Argument
HumanismAn intellectual stance focusing on human values, agency, and rationality; traditionally involves belief in universal human qualities.Battersby defends humanism as inescapable, arguing that it accommodates human experience and content-involving capacities (555-556).
Pragmatic-Pluralist HumanismA modern, flexible interpretation of humanism that emphasizes a pluralistic approach to truth and rationality without absolute guarantees.Battersby advocates for this form, which acknowledges human agency and rationality without essentialist constraints (560-561).
Metaphysics of PresenceThe philosophical belief in a stable, determinate reality that language can directly represent.Battersby critiques this, arguing that while direct access to reality may be impossible, meaningful reference still exists (561-562).
RelativismThe belief that truth and moral values are not absolute but vary by culture, context, or personal perspective.Battersby critiques relativism, asserting that some shared human principles make intercultural critique and understanding possible (565).
Social ConstructionismThe idea that reality, including knowledge and categories, is constructed by social processes and power relations, rather than being an objective fact.Battersby notes social constructionism’s critique of humanism but maintains that human agency and shared values persist (558).
PostmodernismA theoretical stance that questions grand narratives, absolute truths, and stable meaning, viewing knowledge and reality as subjective and fragmented.Battersby positions postmodernism as critical of humanism’s universal claims, yet sees limitations in postmodern relativism (558-559).
Knowledge/Power RelationsA Foucauldian concept that sees knowledge as intertwined with power, influencing societal norms and perceptions of truth.Battersby examines this concept to illustrate humanism’s role as a counterpoint to purely power-driven perspectives (558).
Universalism vs. ParticularismThe debate over whether certain truths, values, or principles are universally applicable or culturally specific.Battersby defends universalism to some extent, citing shared human capacities as a basis for intercultural communication (565-566).
IntentionalityA term in philosophy referring to the directedness or purposefulness of thoughts and perceptions toward objects, events, or states of affairs.Battersby asserts that intentionality supports humanism by demonstrating the role of agency in constructing meaning (563).
Objective vs. Subjective TruthThe distinction between truth as universally applicable (objective) and truth as dependent on individual or cultural perspective (subjective).Battersby argues for a balanced view, where certain truths are context-dependent but communicable across cultural lines (564).
FoundationalismThe philosophical stance that there are basic, self-evident principles or foundations on which knowledge is built.Battersby criticizes foundationalism as inflexible, favoring pragmatic humanism that evolves through human engagement (561).
Cultural CritiqueThe practice of analyzing and challenging cultural norms, values, and assumptions, often to reveal power dynamics.Battersby views humanism as providing a basis for cultural critique without descending into complete relativism (565).
EssentialismThe belief that certain qualities or traits are inherent, natural, and defining for particular groups or categories.Battersby opposes essentialism, advocating for human universals based on shared cognitive capacities rather than fixed essences (562).
Contribution of “The Inescapability of Humanism” by James L. Battersby to Literary Theory/Theories
  1. Humanism in Contemporary Theory
    Battersby revitalizes the relevance of humanism in literary theory, arguing that despite critiques from postmodernism, humanism remains essential for engaging with literature and understanding human experience. He repositions humanism as “inescapable,” emphasizing that literary analysis benefits from recognizing universal human capacities and cognitive structures (Battersby 555-556). This approach reinforces humanism’s adaptability and challenges claims that it is outdated or incompatible with modern critique.
  2. Pragmatism and Pluralism in Literary Criticism
    Battersby’s “pragmatic-pluralist” humanism draws heavily on pragmatist theories, especially the works of Hilary Putnam. He suggests that literary interpretations must be adaptable, evolving through a pluralistic approach that accommodates multiple perspectives without rigid foundationalism. This contribution aligns with pragmatist views on truth and rationality, offering a framework for literary critics to assess interpretations based on their usefulness, coherence, and adaptability, rather than absolute standards (Battersby 560-561).
  3. Critique of Relativism
    In response to the relativism prevalent in postmodernism, Battersby argues that shared cognitive capacities enable meaningful intercultural critique. He contends that extreme relativism undermines the possibility of literary criticism and cross-cultural understanding by denying objective standards. By advocating for “shared forms of reason” based on common human experiences, he contributes to a middle ground in literary theory that opposes both absolutism and extreme relativism (Battersby 565-566).
  4. Social Constructionism and Power Dynamics
    Battersby acknowledges the critiques of humanism from social constructionism, which views reality as a product of power and knowledge relations (Battersby 558). While he agrees that human experience is influenced by social structures, he argues against the complete reduction of human agency. By integrating elements of social constructionism with humanist theory, Battersby’s work contributes to a nuanced literary theory that considers social influences while still valuing human agency and intentionality.
  5. Response to Postmodernism and Deconstruction
    Battersby addresses postmodern and deconstructive theories that challenge fixed meanings and objective truths. He critiques the notion that humanism inherently supports “ontotheological” or logocentric thinking, instead proposing a form of humanism compatible with interpretive flexibility. By doing so, he broadens the applicability of humanism in literary theory, showing that it can coexist with some postmodern insights while resisting its more radical skepticism (Battersby 558-559).
  6. Universalism and the Possibility of Intercultural Criticism
    Battersby’s defense of human universals offers a significant contribution to theories that question the possibility of universal truths. He argues that shared cognitive structures, such as rationality and basic conceptual capacities, provide a foundation for intercultural communication and criticism. This approach contributes to global literary theory by proposing that certain cognitive traits, such as the ability to “translate” and understand other cultures, make meaningful critique possible across cultural boundaries (Battersby 565).
  7. Intentionality and Agency in Literary Interpretation
    Battersby’s emphasis on intentionality aligns with theories that stress the role of human agency in creating and interpreting meaning. He contends that human cognition inherently involves intentionality, allowing us to refer meaningfully to objects and events beyond language. This view supports a humanist approach to literature, emphasizing that literary interpretation is not merely the product of social constructions or linguistic systems but also involves individual and collective agency (Battersby 563).
Examples of Critiques Through “The Inescapability of Humanism” by James L. Battersby
Literary WorkCritique ApproachExample Critique Using Battersby’s Humanism
Hamlet by William ShakespeareHumanist Interpretation of CharacterUsing Battersby’s humanism, Hamlet’s existential questioning about life, death, and morality can be seen as resonating with universal human concerns. Battersby’s concept of “pragmatic-pluralist” humanism allows Hamlet’s introspection to be read as a fundamental human struggle (Battersby 560-561).
Things Fall Apart by Chinua AchebeCultural Critique and Universal ValuesBattersby’s approach would interpret Achebe’s depiction of Igbo culture’s resistance to colonialism as illustrating universal themes of identity, justice, and resilience. This perspective supports the idea that cultural critique can highlight shared human values across societies (Battersby 565).
One Hundred Years of Solitude by Gabriel Garcia MarquezCritique of Relativism in Theme AnalysisBattersby’s rejection of extreme relativism supports reading Marquez’s exploration of memory, family, and history as universally relevant. Themes in the novel are accessible beyond the Colombian context, appealing to universal aspects of human experience (Battersby 566).
Beloved by Toni MorrisonAgency and Intentionality in NarrativeThrough Battersby’s emphasis on agency and intentionality, Sethe’s choices in Beloved can be interpreted as acts of resistance and personal will. This humanist approach validates her decisions as expressions of individual agency within oppressive societal structures (Battersby 563).
Criticism Against “The Inescapability of Humanism” by James L. Battersby
  • Over-Reliance on Universality
    Critics might argue that Battersby’s emphasis on universal human capacities oversimplifies cultural differences, potentially ignoring the complexities of diverse worldviews and experiences.
  • Resistance to Postmodern Insights
    Battersby’s defense of humanism may be seen as resistant to valuable postmodern critiques of foundationalism, such as deconstruction’s exploration of unstable meaning, which questions fixed interpretations and reveals the inherent multiplicity of texts.
  • Underestimation of Social Constructionism
    Battersby’s pragmatic humanism may downplay the influence of social constructs on individual agency, arguably overlooking the extent to which identity, values, and meaning are shaped by societal structures and power dynamics.
  • Limited Acknowledgment of Relativism’s Merits
    While Battersby critiques extreme relativism, critics may argue that he underestimates its potential for promoting tolerance and understanding of cultural differences, which can foster greater inclusivity in literary theory and interpretation.
  • Potential Essentialism in Human Universals
    Although Battersby rejects essentialism, his focus on shared human cognitive traits and capacities might inadvertently echo essentialist ideas, implying that certain qualities are intrinsic to all humans despite cultural and historical variations.
  • Overlooked Agency of Non-Western Perspectives
    Critics may contend that Battersby’s humanism, rooted in Western intellectual traditions, risks marginalizing non-Western perspectives that challenge the very foundation of humanist assumptions, potentially reinforcing a Eurocentric approach to literary theory.
Representative Quotations from “The Inescapability of Humanism” by James L. Battersby with Explanation
QuotationExplanation
“Humanism… is inescapable for creatures with content-involving capacities such as ours” (555).Battersby argues that humans inherently need humanistic values because they are necessary to give meaning and content to our lives, making humanism unavoidable.
“Just as there is no such thing as history, only histories, so there is no humanism, only humanisms” (556).Battersby suggests that humanism is not a monolithic concept but rather an array of diverse perspectives and forms, similar to how history is composed of various narratives.
“It is coextensive with Western intellectual history, [and therefore] humanism is inescapable” (557).This statement emphasizes that humanism has been deeply embedded in Western thought throughout history, making it a persistent and unavoidable part of the intellectual landscape.
“The metaphysics of presence… a belief in our ability to hook our thoughts and language on to things as they really are” (559).Battersby critiques the traditional metaphysical belief that language and thought can directly represent reality, arguing that this is a flawed aspect of older humanist thought.
“Pragmatic pluralism… would be the last to say that there is not much powerful sense in the critique” (560).Battersby acknowledges critiques of humanism, especially how Enlightenment values have been misused, but proposes that a pluralistic, pragmatic approach to humanism can address these concerns constructively.
“There are only the various points of view of actual persons which reflect the various interests and purposes that their theories and descriptions subserve” (560).Citing Hilary Putnam, Battersby underscores a pragmatic perspective that recognizes knowledge as always shaped by individual perspectives and interests, emphasizing the subjective element in human understanding.
“Once we have given up on metaphysical realism… we can free ourselves to get on with the sort of referring and meaning we do anyway with a clear conscience” (563).Battersby suggests that abandoning rigid metaphysical beliefs allows for a more flexible and practical approach to understanding and interacting with the world, a key aspect of his pragmatic humanism.
“Our criticism can only be offered from within our tradition or culture” (566).Battersby argues that cultural critique must come from within a shared cultural framework, making cross-cultural criticism possible through intercultural standards and values.
“To have a thought or a world to talk about or be aware of, we must of necessity participate in systems of rationality” (567).This line underscores Battersby’s belief that rationality is fundamental to human experience, supporting his idea that humanism is essential for meaningful engagement with the world.
“Those who would deny the enduring value and significance of humanism… implicate themselves in pragmatic inconsistency” (567).Battersby concludes that attempts to refute humanism are self-contradictory, as such denials still rely on the rational, intentional systems that humanism encompasses.
Suggested Readings: “The Inescapability of Humanism” by James L. Battersby
  1. Battersby, James L. “The Inescapability of Humanism.” College English, vol. 58, no. 5, 1996, pp. 555–67. JSTOR, https://doi.org/10.2307/378756. Accessed 13 Nov. 2024.
  2. Rae, Gavin. “Re-Thinking the Human: Heidegger, Fundamental Ontology, and Humanism.” Human Studies, vol. 33, no. 1, 2010, pp. 23–39. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/40981088. Accessed 13 Nov. 2024.
  3. Wolff, Ernst. “Levinas’ Post-Anti-Humanist Humanism: Humanism of the Other.” Political Responsibility for a Globalised World: After Levinas’ Humanism, transcript Verlag, 2011, pp. 105–46. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/j.ctv1xxsvc.10. Accessed 13 Nov. 2024.
  4. Manne, Kate. “Humanism: A Critique.” Social Theory and Practice, vol. 42, no. 2, 2016, pp. 389–415. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/24871349. Accessed 13 Nov. 2024.

“Problems of Literary Theory: The Problem of Meaning” by Catherine Belsey: Summary and Critique

“Problems of Literary Theory: The Problem of Meaning” by Catherine Belsey first appeared in 1982 in New Literary History as part of a special issue on the challenges within literary theory.

"Problems of Literary Theory: The Problem of Meaning" by Catherine Belsey: Summary and Critique
Introduction: “Problems of Literary Theory: The Problem of Meaning” by Catherine Belsey

“Problems of Literary Theory: The Problem of Meaning” by Catherine Belsey first appeared in 1982 in New Literary History as part of a special issue on the challenges within literary theory. In this article, Belsey addresses the critical problem of meaning, which she argues is a central concern in literary criticism. By examining different theoretical frameworks—empiricism, formalism, and poststructuralism—Belsey explores how each perspective conceptualizes meaning in varied, often conflicting ways. She posits that these disputes highlight the theoretical nature of interpretation itself, where meaning is not merely found within a text but is actively constructed through critical frameworks influenced by language, ideology, and cultural contexts. The work gained popularity due to its incisive critique of traditional literary methods and its accessible analysis of complex theoretical issues. Belsey’s arguments resonated widely, encouraging critics to rethink the assumptions underlying literary interpretation, making this work foundational in debates about objectivity, the role of the critic, and the very nature of meaning in literature.

Summary of “Problems of Literary Theory: The Problem of Meaning” by Catherine Belsey
  • Central Problem of Literary Theory: The Problem of Meaning
    Catherine Belsey begins by framing the central issue of literary theory as the “problem of meaning,” noting that this question of meaning is crucial to literary criticism across different approaches (Belsey, 1982, p. 175). Meaning is contested not only in its definition but also in its implications for how critics interpret texts. Belsey points out that literary theory’s divisions—between empiricism, formalism, and poststructuralism—reflect fundamentally different views on how meaning is constructed and understood (p. 176).
  • Challenges of Neutrality in Literary Criticism
    Belsey argues that there is no “neutral place” from which to conduct literary criticism without engaging with theoretical assumptions about meaning (p. 176). Ignoring theoretical questions leads to a reliance on “unexamined assumptions,” an issue she sees as pervasive and problematic in the field. She critiques the notion that literary competence or appreciation can provide a non-theoretical foundation for criticism, as advocated by some critics, such as Stein Haugom Olsen (p. 177).
  • Plurality of Textual Meaning
    Addressing the debate on textual interpretation, Belsey highlights Jeffrey Stout’s argument that multiple interpretations of a text—such as Marxist, Freudian, or theological readings—do not necessarily compete but can coexist by focusing on different aspects (p. 177). She emphasizes that recognizing this plurality enriches criticism by acknowledging that there is no single, fixed meaning in a text.
  • Theoretical Critiques of Objective Meaning
    Belsey critiques attempts to ascribe fixed or “obvious” meanings to literary works. She notes the complexity of meaning within texts, where even seemingly clear sentences can yield diverse interpretations. She uses examples from works by Shakespeare and Yeats to illustrate that meanings often require contextualization and are subject to cultural and historical influences (p. 178).
  • Role of Language in Constructing Meaning
    Drawing on Saussure’s model of the sign, Belsey underscores that language itself is a crucial site of meaning construction. In her view, language signifies through relational and cultural processes, aligning with poststructuralist theories that view meaning as fluid and context-dependent (p. 180). By connecting this view to Derrida’s concept of différance, Belsey suggests that the meanings of words are never fully fixed, always carrying multiple, historically situated interpretations (p. 181).
  • Influence of Power in Interpretation
    Belsey introduces Michel Foucault’s ideas to emphasize that interpretations of texts are not neutral but often reflect power dynamics. According to Foucault, knowledge and meaning are produced within institutions that enforce specific interpretations and practices, affecting how literary texts are read and understood (p. 181). For Belsey, Foucault offers a framework that allows literary criticism to pursue a transformative role by analyzing how power shapes meaning.
  • Implications for Literary Criticism
    Belsey concludes by discussing the implications of adopting a Foucauldian approach, which challenges the objectivity of criticism. She suggests that such an approach would expand the scope of criticism beyond traditional aesthetic evaluations, focusing instead on texts’ capacity to reveal the fluidity of meanings and their sociopolitical contexts. This perspective, Belsey argues, would reframe criticism as a practice not of finding fixed meanings but of understanding how meanings and values are constructed and contested (p. 182).
Literary Terms/Concepts in “Problems of Literary Theory: The Problem of Meaning” by Catherine Belsey
Concept/TermExplanation
MeaningCentral issue in literary theory; Belsey explores how meaning is constructed through different theoretical frameworks, with no fixed or objective interpretation.
EmpiricismApproach focusing on observable facts, often associated with intuitive interpretation of texts, critiqued by Belsey for avoiding deeper theoretical questioning.
FormalismA method focusing on the form and structure of texts, treating meaning as inherent in literary form itself, independent of historical or social contexts.
PoststructuralismA critical framework that views meaning as unstable and context-dependent, questioning the fixed interpretations of traditional criticism.
Plurality of MeaningConcept that texts do not have a single, fixed meaning but instead support multiple interpretations based on the reader’s theoretical perspective.
Signifier and SignifiedSaussurean terms for the components of linguistic signs; “signifier” is the form of the word, while “signified” is its meaning, which is contextually constructed.
DifféranceDerridean concept suggesting that meaning is deferred and relational, never fully present or fixed, making interpretation a continuous process.
TextualityRefers to the qualities and structures within a text that shape how it is interpreted, often seen in poststructuralist theory as inherently unstable.
Power and KnowledgeFoucault’s idea that knowledge production, including literary interpretation, is intertwined with power dynamics within societal institutions.
IdeologyBelsey’s exploration of how meanings within texts reflect and challenge ideological structures, showing that interpretation is influenced by cultural beliefs.
Reader-Response TheoryTheory that considers readers’ role in creating meaning, suggesting that interpretations are shaped by individual and cultural perspectives.
DeconstructionDerrida’s approach to examining texts by uncovering inherent contradictions, emphasizing the multiplicity and instability of meaning.
StructuralismFramework focusing on underlying structures (linguistic or social) that shape meaning, which poststructuralism critiques for assuming stable meanings.
Critique of ObjectivityBelsey challenges the idea that criticism can be objective or neutral, arguing instead that interpretations are shaped by theoretical assumptions.
Interpretive FrameworksTheories or perspectives (e.g., Marxist, Freudian) that influence how critics understand and derive meaning from texts.
Hypostasized MeaningConcept of meaning as an assumed “essence” that can exist outside language, critiqued by Belsey for implying fixed truths without theoretical grounding.
Contribution of “Problems of Literary Theory: The Problem of Meaning” by Catherine Belsey to Literary Theory/Theories

1. Poststructuralism

  • Contribution: Belsey advances poststructuralist thought by arguing that meaning in texts is not fixed or inherent but rather constructed through interpretive practices. She critiques the idea of a singular, stable meaning, supporting Derrida’s concept of différance, which posits that meaning is always deferred and relational (Belsey, 1982, p. 181).
  • Reference: Belsey highlights that poststructuralism offers a productive model for understanding texts, as meaning is seen as fluid, “always in process, always contextually deferred” (p. 180).

2. Structuralism and Saussurean Linguistics

  • Contribution: Using Saussure’s model of the sign (signifier and signified), Belsey builds on structuralist principles to emphasize that meaning is created through language itself, not by external reference or authorial intent. She critiques interpretations that assume a “real presence” of meaning within a text, instead positioning language as the core of meaning construction (p. 180).
  • Reference: Belsey draws directly from Saussure’s ideas, stating, “language itself which signifies,” and hence, it is the “location of meaning” rather than any inherent essence (p. 180).

3. Reader-Response Theory

  • Contribution: Belsey contributes to reader-response theory by addressing the role of readers in creating meaning. She argues that each reader brings their own interpretive framework, leading to plural and varied meanings based on personal, cultural, or theoretical perspectives (p. 177). This plurality underscores that meaning arises in the interaction between text and reader.
  • Reference: Belsey refers to the multiple interpretations that readers may apply, noting that “readings are not necessarily in competition with each other…there is no single meaning” (p. 177).

4. Ideological Criticism and Cultural Studies

  • Contribution: Belsey’s examination of meaning also contributes to ideological criticism by challenging the neutrality of interpretations. She suggests that texts reflect ideological positions and power structures, as in Foucault’s assertion that knowledge, including literary interpretation, is inherently linked to power (p. 181). This approach has influenced cultural studies by connecting literary meaning with sociopolitical and institutional contexts.
  • Reference: She asserts that meaning cannot be separated from its ideological implications, stating that the problem of meaning is “centrally a debate about meaning” and its ideological influences (p. 175).

5. Deconstruction

  • Contribution: Belsey’s critique of objective meaning is aligned with Derridean deconstruction, questioning stable interpretations and examining texts for internal contradictions. By rejecting the notion of a single, inherent meaning, she encourages a deconstructive reading that exposes multiple meanings and the limits of language (p. 181).
  • Reference: She suggests that meaning is “never single, never fixed,” emphasizing deconstruction’s role in destabilizing absolute interpretations (p. 182).

6. Foucauldian Discourse Analysis

  • Contribution: Belsey draws from Michel Foucault’s ideas on discourse to argue that literary criticism is itself a discourse shaped by power. By treating meaning as a product of institutional forces, she links literary theory to Foucault’s concept of knowledge as power, proposing a critical approach that investigates how texts function within larger ideological systems (p. 181).
  • Reference: She states that meaning in texts is “produced in institutions” and is “a network of signifieds” that often serves power, supporting a Foucauldian analysis of literary texts as products of cultural power dynamics (p. 181).

7. Empiricism Critique

  • Contribution: Belsey critiques empiricist approaches that claim to objectively evaluate texts without theoretical bias, which she argues are based on “unexamined assumptions.” By revealing that all interpretations are theoretically and ideologically influenced, Belsey challenges empiricism’s claims of objectivity and promotes a more self-aware, theoretically grounded criticism (p. 176).
  • Reference: Belsey warns against “falling back on unexamined assumptions” that empiricist criticism relies on, suggesting that true neutrality in interpretation is impossible (p. 176).

8. Formalism Critique

  • Contribution: By questioning the inherent meaning in a text’s form or structure, Belsey challenges formalism’s emphasis on the text as an isolated entity. Instead, she argues that form and structure gain meaning only through the interpretive frameworks applied by readers, which vary according to cultural and ideological contexts (p. 176).
  • Reference: She asserts that interpretations should not be “intuitive, explicitly antitheoretical,” critiquing formalist ideas that elevate the text’s form above cultural context (p. 177).
Examples of Critiques Through “Problems of Literary Theory: The Problem of Meaning” by Catherine Belsey
Literary WorkApplication of Belsey’s TheoryExample of Critique
Hamlet by William ShakespearePlurality of Meaning & Reader Interpretation Belsey’s emphasis on plural readings suggests that Hamlet allows for multiple interpretations depending on readers’ theoretical lenses.A Marxist reading may interpret Hamlet’s hesitation as reflecting class struggles and power dynamics, while a Freudian analysis might focus on psychological conflicts, showing that meaning shifts based on interpretive frameworks.
Pride and Prejudice by Jane AustenIdeology and Cultural Context Belsey’s framework highlights how texts reflect and challenge cultural ideologies. Pride and Prejudice offers critiques of class and gender roles.By focusing on Elizabeth Bennet’s rejection of societal expectations, a feminist reading aligns with Belsey’s view on ideological critique, examining how meaning shifts with changing perceptions of gender and power.
The Waste Land by T.S. EliotInstability of Meaning & Deconstruction Belsey’s support for Derrida’s différance aligns with the fragmented nature of Eliot’s poem, where meaning is deferred and elusive.The Waste Land can be critiqued as resisting a single interpretation; its fragmented structure and intertextuality invite a poststructuralist reading, which sees meaning as always deferred, aligning with Belsey’s ideas on textual instability.
Beloved by Toni MorrisonPower Dynamics & Foucauldian Discourse Belsey’s Foucauldian view suggests analyzing how Morrison’s novel constructs identity and power within cultural memory and historical trauma.A critique using Belsey’s approach would explore how Beloved reveals the power structures surrounding race and memory, examining how the text constructs meanings around identity, survival, and history through competing discourses.
Criticism Against “Problems of Literary Theory: The Problem of Meaning” by Catherine Belsey
  • Overemphasis on Theoretical Relativism
    Some critics argue that Belsey’s focus on the instability and plurality of meaning undermines the possibility of definitive interpretation, potentially rendering any textual analysis as equally valid or invalid, which could dilute critical rigor.
  • Limited Practical Application
    Belsey’s theoretical insights, while intellectually stimulating, are sometimes criticized for being challenging to apply practically in literary analysis, leaving critics without clear methodologies for analyzing specific texts.
  • Neglect of Authorial Intent
    Belsey’s disregard for authorial intent has been criticized as limiting; some argue that understanding an author’s purpose can enhance rather than constrain the interpretation, offering insights into cultural and historical contexts.
  • Dismissal of Empirical Criticism
    Belsey’s critique of empiricism as overly simplistic and reliant on “unexamined assumptions” has been contested by critics who believe that empirical methods can offer valuable insights and that objectivity, while complex, is not entirely unattainable.
  • Ideological Bias in Criticism
    Critics note that Belsey’s emphasis on ideology and power structures risks politicizing literary criticism excessively, potentially sidelining aesthetic and literary qualities of the text in favor of ideological readings.
  • Dependency on Poststructuralist Theories
    Belsey’s reliance on poststructuralist thinkers like Derrida and Foucault has been critiqued for potentially limiting her theoretical framework. Critics argue that this dependency could close off alternative interpretative frameworks, especially those outside postmodernist thought.
  • Potential for Reader Subjectivity Overload
    By endorsing the plurality of reader responses, Belsey’s approach may be seen as enabling overly subjective readings, where the reader’s biases dominate the text’s meaning, raising concerns about relativism in literary criticism.
Representative Quotations from “Problems of Literary Theory: The Problem of Meaning” by Catherine Belsey with Explanation
QuotationExplanation
“The central problem of literary theory is the problem of meaning.”Belsey identifies meaning as the primary concern in literary theory, emphasizing that understanding how meaning operates in literature is foundational to all other critical analysis.
“To ignore the theoretical question is simply to fall back on unexamined assumptions.”This statement highlights the necessity of engaging with theoretical questions about meaning rather than relying on intuitive or simplistic understandings.
“Meaning is conventionally hypostasized, a real presence, never quite defined, understood as other than language itself, but the source, paradoxically, from which language derives its substance, its life.”Belsey critiques the conventional notion of meaning as something abstract and separate from language, urging that meaning and language are inseparable and contextually grounded.
“The question ‘What is the meaning of a text?’ might elicit answers of various kinds, in terms of the author’s intention, the external relation of the text, or the discourse the reader brings to bear on the text in the process of producing a reading.”This highlights the multiplicity of interpretations that can emerge from a text, emphasizing that meaning is not fixed but contingent on different interpretative frameworks.
“Texts are (or can be) interesting: ‘The more interesting the text, the more readings we shall be able to give.'”Belsey suggests that the complexity and richness of a text lead to multiple readings, and this plurality is part of what makes texts compelling in literary criticism.
“The specter of a pure, conceptual intelligibility, a ‘truth in the soul,’ as Derrida puts it, of which words are only an expression, is at the heart of our problems.”Here, Belsey engages with Derrida’s view on the instability of meaning, where meaning is always deferred and cannot be pinned down to a singular, unchanging concept.
“The more interesting the text, the more readings we shall be able to give.”This underlines the idea that engaging with a text can lead to varied interpretations, and texts with rich layers of meaning allow for a multiplicity of critical perspectives.
“For Foucault the signified is inscribed in knowledges which are repositories simultaneously of meaning and power.”Belsey integrates Foucault’s theory, emphasizing how meaning is not only linguistic but also shaped by power structures and historical context, affecting how knowledge is produced and interpreted.
“A knowledge (or a discourse) is a network of signifieds, and these meanings may conflict with those delimited by the same signifiers in other knowledges.”This refers to the concept that meaning is fluid and context-dependent, and the same words or ideas can hold different meanings in different discourses or knowledge systems.
“The alternative I am proposing is not a return to ‘objective criticism’ but a move beyond the empiricist framework of ideas, which gives us a world consisting only of subjects and objects, into a problematic where meaning is not spectral and singular but substantial and plural.”Belsey critiques both traditional objective criticism and the overly subjective framework of literary theory, proposing a more nuanced view of meaning as plural and dynamic, produced in the interplay of power and language.
Suggested Readings: “Problems of Literary Theory: The Problem of Meaning” by Catherine Belsey
  1. Belsey, Catherine. “Problems of Literary Theory: The Problem of Meaning.” New Literary History, vol. 14, no. 1, 1982, pp. 175–82. JSTOR, https://doi.org/10.2307/468964. Accessed 13 Nov. 2024.
  2. Jauss, Hans Robert, and Elizabeth Benzinger. “Literary History as a Challenge to Literary Theory.” New Literary History, vol. 2, no. 1, 1970, pp. 7–37. JSTOR, https://doi.org/10.2307/468585. Accessed 13 Nov. 2024.
  3. Rowlett, John L., editor. “Reviewing Criticism: Literary Theory.” Genre Theory and Historical Change: Theoretical Essays of Ralph Cohen, University of Virginia Press, 2017, pp. 122–36. JSTOR, https://doi.org/10.2307/j.ctt1v2xtv6.12. Accessed 13 Nov. 2024.
  4. Nicholas O. Pagan. “The Evolution of Literary Theory and the Literary Mind.” Interdisciplinary Literary Studies, vol. 15, no. 2, 2013, pp. 157–79. JSTOR, https://doi.org/10.5325/intelitestud.15.2.0157. Accessed 13 Nov. 2024.

“Literary History as a Challenge to Literary Theory” by Hans Robert Jauss and Elizabeth Benzinger: Summary and Critique

“Literary History as a Challenge to Literary Theory” by Hans Robert Jauss and translated by Elizabeth Benzinger first appeared in New Literary History, Vol. 2, No. 1, as part of a symposium on literary history in Autumn 1970.

"Literary History as a Challenge to Literary Theory" by Hans Robert Jauss and Elizabeth Benzinger: Summary and Critique
Introduction: “Literary History as a Challenge to Literary Theory” by Hans Robert Jauss and Elizabeth Benzinger

“Literary History as a Challenge to Literary Theory” by Hans Robert Jauss and translated by Elizabeth Benzinger first appeared in New Literary History, Vol. 2, No. 1, as part of a symposium on literary history in Autumn 1970. This influential essay presents a framework that reconsiders literary history’s role in relation to literary theory, urging a shift away from solely formalist or Marxist interpretations. Jauss critiques these schools for treating literature as a closed system, ignoring its interactive and socially impactful dimension, especially its reception by audiences. By proposing an “aesthetics of reception,” Jauss argues that literature’s value and historicity derive not only from its creation but also from its engagement with readers over time. This “dialogue” between text and reader forms a living history that changes as each generation interprets literature anew, bridging historical and aesthetic analysis.

The essay’s importance lies in its challenge to prevailing views that literature’s meaning and value are inherent and static, as well as in its proposal of a dynamic model where the audience plays a pivotal role in literary continuity and historical impact. This approach reshapes literary theory by grounding it in human experience, making it integral to cultural and historical understanding. Jauss’s ideas significantly influenced the field of reader-response criticism and expanded the methodological toolkit of literary historians, marking a progressive turn towards contextual, socially engaged literary analysis.

Summary of “Literary History as a Challenge to Literary Theory” by Hans Robert Jauss and Elizabeth Benzinger
  • Literary History’s Role in Bridging Theory and Reception: Jauss critiques both Marxist and formalist approaches to literary theory for ignoring the audience’s role in the literary experience. He advocates a literary history that integrates the audience’s reception and interaction with texts, acknowledging their active role in shaping a work’s historical impact (Jauss, p. 7).
  • Audience as Historical Agent: Rather than treating the reader as a passive recipient, Jauss argues that the audience is a “history-making energy” that transforms a work through reception. Literature achieves continuity through this evolving relationship with readers over time (Jauss, p. 8).
  • The Aesthetics of Reception: Jauss introduces the aesthetics of reception as a new framework, suggesting that literary history should be viewed as a dialogue between past works and the evolving public perception. This perspective allows literature to maintain relevance across generations by adapting and responding to new interpretive contexts (Jauss, p. 10).
  • Horizon of Expectations and Aesthetic Distance: The concept of a “horizon of expectations” is central, as it defines the frame within which readers interpret new works based on previous experiences and genres. The aesthetic value of a text, according to Jauss, can be measured by the extent to which it challenges or expands this horizon, creating “aesthetic distance” (Jauss, p. 12).
  • Evolutionary Process in Literary Development: Jauss asserts that literary history is not linear but evolves through a dynamic process of reception and reinterpretation. This ongoing “literary evolution” reshapes old forms as new works provide fresh perspectives, influencing both current literary norms and historical canons (Jauss, p. 17).
  • Synchronic and Diachronic Analysis of Literature: Jauss proposes integrating both synchronic (cross-sectional) and diachronic (historical) analyses to understand literature within its broader social and historical contexts. This combined approach can reveal how works are situated within and respond to their immediate literary environment while influencing future interpretations (Jauss, p. 30).
  • Impact of Literature on Social and Ethical Norms: Literature’s social function goes beyond mere representation, as Jauss argues it plays a role in shaping moral and social values by challenging prevailing standards. Through this lens, literature actively participates in defining societal ethics rather than merely reflecting them (Jauss, p. 35).
  • Beyond Mimesis to a Societal Function of Literature: Moving beyond traditional aesthetics, Jauss asserts that literature’s role in society is to provoke reflection and offer alternative viewpoints, thus fostering critical thought and potentially inspiring societal change (Jauss, p. 37).
Theoretical Terms/Concepts in “Literary History as a Challenge to Literary Theory” by Hans Robert Jauss and Elizabeth Benzinger
Theoretical Term/ConceptDefinitionExplanation/Context in the Text
Aesthetics of ReceptionA framework that centers on the reader’s experience, emphasizing the role of reception in the historical and aesthetic life of a text.Jauss suggests that the value and meaning of literature are actively shaped by its audience, not only by the author or text itself. This approach positions the reader’s interaction as essential to understanding literature as a historical process (Jauss, p. 8).
Horizon of ExpectationsThe collective set of cultural, social, and aesthetic norms and expectations that shape how readers interpret and respond to a work.A work’s impact is measured by how it aligns with, challenges, or redefines these expectations, creating “aesthetic distance” based on the level of novelty and deviation from prior norms (Jauss, p. 12).
Aesthetic DistanceThe gap between a reader’s existing expectations and the experience offered by a new work, reflecting the degree of novelty or challenge posed by the text.Jauss argues that works with high aesthetic distance stimulate reader engagement by provoking new perspectives. The “greater” the distance, the more the work challenges norms and encourages reflective reception (Jauss, p. 12).
Literary EvolutionThe dynamic process by which literature develops over time through the ongoing interaction of reception, interpretation, and creation.This evolutionary approach contrasts with linear or teleological models, as it sees literature developing through complex dialogues between old and new works, shaped by reader response and historical context (Jauss, p. 17).
Synchronic AnalysisA method of studying literature at a single historical moment, analyzing how works interact within a common cultural or literary horizon.Jauss advocates synchronic cross-sections to examine how contemporary works resonate with or differ from each other, revealing a system of relationships within a specific time period (Jauss, p. 30).
Diachronic AnalysisAnalyzing literature as it develops over time, focusing on historical progression and transformations in literary forms and reader responses.Jauss suggests combining diachronic and synchronic analysis to trace both the evolution of genres and the shifting patterns of reader reception, offering a fuller picture of literary history (Jauss, p. 30).
Impact HistoryThe history of a work’s influence, tracking how it has been received, interpreted, and integrated into cultural and literary norms over time.This concept supports the idea that literary history includes the progression of responses to a text, showing its evolving role in shaping cultural and aesthetic values (Jauss, p. 31).
ClassicalRefers to works that transcend historical distance and maintain relevance across time, often seen as possessing inherent “timeless” value.Jauss challenges this static view by suggesting that a work becomes classical only through continued reinterpretation by successive generations, underscoring the role of historical mediation in constructing “classics” (Jauss, p. 23).
Social Function of LiteratureLiterature’s ability to influence and shape societal values, norms, and ethics, extending beyond its role as mere representation of social realities.According to Jauss, literature can redefine morals by challenging prevailing norms, as shown by works that evoke moral or ethical reconsideration within the reader, often inspiring societal shifts (Jauss, p. 35).
Question and Answer StructureA hermeneutic method where literature is understood as posing questions that invite reader response, aligning with Gadamer’s idea of historical dialogue.For Jauss, each work embodies questions pertinent to its time, which may only be fully realized in new contexts. Readers must interpret literature by engaging with its implied questions, thereby linking past and present meanings (Jauss, p. 22).
Genre HorizonThe set of formal and thematic conventions associated with a particular genre that shapes how readers approach a text.Jauss argues that new works often engage with the “genre horizon,” either conforming to or challenging these conventions, which shifts the reader’s expectations and redefines genre boundaries (Jauss, p. 14).
Impersonal Narrative FormA narrative technique that presents characters’ thoughts and feelings without explicit narrative commentary, leaving moral interpretation to the reader.Jauss discusses Flaubert’s use of this style in Madame Bovary, highlighting how it subverted moral norms and invited readers to question accepted values, thus serving as an example of literature’s social function (Jauss, p. 35).
Contribution of “Literary History as a Challenge to Literary Theory” by Hans Robert Jauss and Elizabeth Benzinger to Literary Theory/Theories

1. Reception Theory

  • Contribution: Jauss is considered a pioneer in reception theory, where he challenges the conventional focus on the author and text alone by placing the reader’s response at the center of literary analysis. He argues that literary meaning is not fixed but changes with each generation’s reception.
  • Key Concept: Horizon of Expectations – This is defined as the framework of cultural and historical norms through which audiences interpret literature. Jauss proposes that the meaning of a text emerges through the reader’s response, shaped by historical context and prior literary experience.
  • Reference: Jauss states, “The historical life of a literary work is unthinkable without the active participation of its audience” (Jauss, p. 8), underscoring the reader’s role in shaping the work’s impact over time.

2. Historicism and Diachronic Analysis in Literary Studies

  • Contribution: Jauss revitalizes literary historicism by introducing a dynamic, evolutionary model for understanding literary development, which contrasts with traditional, linear historicism. He suggests that literature should be understood as part of an ongoing dialogue with both past and future works.
  • Key Concept: Literary Evolution – Jauss’s notion of literary evolution involves tracking the transformation of genres and themes across time through the lens of reader response and societal change.
  • Reference: He explains that literary history should account for the “mutual mediation” of old and new forms, emphasizing literature’s continuous transformation rather than a static historical narrative (Jauss, p. 17).

3. Hermeneutics and Dialogism

  • Contribution: Jauss integrates hermeneutic principles, particularly from Gadamer, into literary theory by framing literary history as a “dialogue” between past and present. This dialogic relationship forms the foundation of understanding literature in a historical and interpretative context.
  • Key Concept: Question and Answer Structure – Inspired by Gadamer’s hermeneutics, Jauss advocates for a method where each text is seen as a response to specific historical and literary questions, requiring the reader to engage with its historical and ethical implications.
  • Reference: Jauss argues that understanding is achieved through “the process of fusion of such horizons which seem to exist independently,” suggesting that readers must actively interpret the questions each text implicitly answers (Jauss, p. 22).

4. Aesthetics and Value of the Classical Canon

  • Contribution: Jauss critiques the concept of the “classical” as a fixed standard, proposing instead that the status of classical works results from their ongoing reinterpretation by successive generations. His challenge to classical aesthetics supports a more fluid, reception-based understanding of literary value.
  • Key Concept: Classical as a Construct – According to Jauss, works become classical not through inherent “timelessness” but through sustained relevance and reinterpretation by later audiences.
  • Reference: Jauss contends, “the concept of the classical which interprets itself” obscures the role of historical reception in determining a work’s status, stressing that classics are products of continual engagement (Jauss, p. 23).

5. Sociology of Literature and the Social Function of Art

  • Contribution: Jauss explores literature’s role in society by examining how it challenges or reinforces social norms. He moves beyond representation theories, suggesting that literature actively shapes societal values and ideas, rather than merely reflecting them.
  • Key Concept: Social Function of Literature – Jauss argues that literature contributes to society by expanding the reader’s moral and ethical imagination, often challenging prevailing norms and fostering new social perspectives.
  • Reference: He illustrates this with Flaubert’s Madame Bovary, which forces readers to re-evaluate their moral judgments, highlighting literature’s power to provoke ethical reflection (Jauss, p. 35).

6. Structuralism and Genre Theory

  • Contribution: Jauss addresses the limitations of structuralist genre theory, particularly in its tendency to treat genres as static categories. He instead views genres as evolving systems that respond to shifting reader expectations and cultural norms.
  • Key Concept: Genre Horizon – Jauss’s concept of genre horizon introduces a dynamic view of genres, where texts not only conform to genre expectations but also reshape and expand them, thereby evolving the genre itself.
  • Reference: Jauss notes, “The new text evokes for the reader (listener) the horizon of expectations and rules familiar from earlier texts, which are then varied, corrected, changed or just reproduced,” pointing to genre as an evolving framework (Jauss, p. 14).

7. Impact History and Historical Consciousness in Literary Theory

  • Contribution: Jauss introduces the idea of “impact history,” proposing that a work’s influence is best understood through the sequence of its reception and reinterpretation over time. This continuous interaction aligns literary history with the evolving consciousness of readers.
  • Key Concept: Impact History – By tracing a work’s impact on successive generations, Jauss’s theory accounts for shifts in cultural significance and literary value over time, focusing on the progression of literary influence.
  • Reference: He states, “The history of literature can be rewritten on this premise,” suggesting that impact history can be a foundation for a revised, reader-centered literary history (Jauss, p. 31).
Examples of Critiques Through “Literary History as a Challenge to Literary Theory” by Hans Robert Jauss and Elizabeth Benzinger
Literary WorkCritique Through Jauss’s FrameworkKey Theoretical LensExplanation & Reference
Madame Bovary by Gustave FlaubertJauss critiques Madame Bovary by focusing on the reception and moral dilemma it presents to readers, emphasizing how Flaubert’s use of impersonal narration forces readers to confront their own judgments.Reception Theory, Social FunctionJauss uses Madame Bovary as an example of how new literary forms like “impersonal telling” create moral ambiguity, making readers question societal norms rather than imposing a moral stance. This narrative style disorients readers, challenging them to interpret the story’s ethical implications (p. 35).
Don Quixote by Miguel de CervantesJauss analyzes Don Quixote as a work that uses parodic genre conventions to reshape audience expectations, evolving the genre of chivalric romance into a critical commentary.Genre Horizon, Evolution of GenresJauss highlights how Don Quixote creates new horizons by parodying familiar conventions, like the chivalric romance, which leads readers to recognize the absurdity of traditional heroic ideals. This challenges and reconstructs genre boundaries for readers of the time (p. 14).
Perceval, the Story of the Grail by Chrétien de TroyesJauss interprets Perceval as a “literary event” rather than a static historical artifact, viewing it as a text that establishes new narrative expectations for the medieval audience.Literary Evolution, Impact HistoryJauss asserts that Perceval introduced complex narrative forms and thematic depth that broke from previous epics. By doing so, it becomes “eventful” only through readers who understand it as an innovative step beyond prior heroic narratives, expanding the genre’s possibilities (p. 10).
Chimères by Gérard de NervalJauss examines Chimères as a work that confronts and subverts Romantic conventions, challenging readers to re-evaluate Romantic ideals and mythic motifs.Horizon of Expectations, Reception TheoryJauss notes that Chimères mixes familiar Romantic symbols with an unsettling sense of existential despair, creating a distance from reader expectations. This horizon shift forces readers to reconsider their Romantic ideals, reflecting Nerval’s own critique of Romanticism’s limitations (p. 16).
Criticism Against “Literary History as a Challenge to Literary Theory” by Hans Robert Jauss and Elizabeth Benzinger
  • Lack of Emphasis on Authorial Intent
    Critics argue that Jauss’s emphasis on reader reception overlooks the importance of authorial intent. By focusing predominantly on the audience’s interpretation, Jauss may diminish the significance of the author’s original purpose and context.
  • Over-Reliance on Subjective Reception
    Reception theory can be seen as overly subjective, as it depends heavily on the audience’s changing perceptions and experiences. Critics suggest this may lead to a relativistic view of literature, where meaning fluctuates excessively with each generation’s reception, undermining the stability of a text’s meaning.
  • Inadequate Engagement with Power Dynamics in Interpretation
    Jauss has been critiqued for not addressing how power structures and social hierarchies impact reader interpretation and reception. This oversight limits the theory’s ability to account for how dominant ideologies might shape and control literary interpretation over time.
  • Insufficient Methodology for Determining Canon
    Jauss’s theory has been critiqued for offering little guidance on evaluating why certain works become canonical while others do not. Critics argue that simply tracking the “horizon of expectations” is inadequate for explaining why certain texts maintain prominence in literary history.
  • Neglect of Cultural and Social Contexts
    By focusing on the aesthetic experience of the reader, Jauss may inadequately account for broader cultural, economic, and social forces that influence both the production and reception of literature. This narrow focus could limit the applicability of his theory across diverse socio-cultural contexts.
  • Limited Applicability to Non-Western Literature
    Reception theory, as formulated by Jauss, has been criticized for its Eurocentric approach, which may not apply as effectively to non-Western literary traditions with different structures of literary history, genre, and audience engagement.
  • Tendency Toward Retrospective Bias
    Jauss’s method of reconstructing past “horizons of expectations” has been criticized for being speculative and prone to retrospective bias. Reconstructing past receptions risks imposing present-day understandings onto historical interpretations.
Representative Quotations from “Literary History as a Challenge to Literary Theory” by Hans Robert Jauss and Elizabeth Benzinger with Explanation
QuotationExplanation
“The historical life of a literary work is unthinkable without the active participation of its audience.”Jauss emphasizes the role of the reader in bringing a text to life and creating its historical relevance, challenging previous theories that focus only on authorial intent and formal structure. He asserts that literature’s impact evolves over time as it interacts with different generations of readers.
“Literary history can be rewritten… by an aesthetics of reception and impact.”This statement highlights Jauss’s belief that literary history should consider the evolving responses and interpretations of audiences rather than adhering strictly to a chronological or stylistic analysis. The reception theory thus calls for a “rewriting” of literary history to include how works affect readers across different times and contexts.
“A literary work is not an object that stands by itself and offers the same face to each reader in each period.”Jauss critiques objectivist approaches to literary analysis, arguing that texts do not have a fixed meaning. Instead, each reader and period brings a unique interpretation, reinforcing the dynamic relationship between the work and its audience.
“The new text evokes for the reader the horizon of expectations and rules familiar from earlier texts.”Jauss introduces the concept of the “horizon of expectations,” where a reader’s prior experiences with literature shape their response to a new work. This “horizon” becomes the basis for evaluating the innovation or predictability of the text, as readers compare it with their past literary experiences.
“Aesthetic distance… is the distance between the given horizon of expectations and the appearance of a new work.”Jauss explains that the “aesthetic distance” between what a reader expects and what a text delivers determines the text’s novelty and artistic value. If a work challenges or negates readers’ expectations, it often requires a shift in their understanding, marking it as innovative.
“The history of literature is a process in which the passive reception of the reader changes into active reception.”This reflects Jauss’s belief that readers do not merely absorb literature passively but engage with it actively over time, responding critically and reshaping their interpretations. This process involves transforming initial responses into deeper critical understandings and even new creative works.
“The specific achievement of literature in society can be found only when the function of literature is not imitation.”Jauss challenges the notion of literature as merely reflecting society, suggesting that it actively influences social beliefs and norms. Literature should be seen as an active force that offers new perspectives and possibilities, going beyond mere representation of existing reality.
“Literary history based on the history of reception and impact reveals itself as a process.”By framing literary history as an ongoing process of reception, Jauss argues that literature evolves not just through the addition of new works but also through continuous reinterpretation by readers and critics. This view treats literary history as dynamic and open-ended rather than static and fixed.
“The perspective of the aesthetics of reception mediates between passive reception and active understanding.”Here, Jauss describes his theory as bridging the gap between simply consuming a text and actively engaging with it. This shift to active understanding occurs when readers interpret, question, and even produce new meanings in response to the text, advancing literary tradition.
“The judgment of the centuries… is the successive development of the potential meaning present in a work.”Jauss refers to the enduring impact and evolution of a work’s meaning over time. Instead of one definitive interpretation, the “judgment of the centuries” reveals how literature accrues significance as different generations uncover new facets and applications, showcasing its lasting value and relevance.
Suggested Readings: “Literary History as a Challenge to Literary Theory” by Hans Robert Jauss and Elizabeth Benzinger
  1. Jauss, Hans Robert, and Elizabeth Benzinger. “Literary History as a Challenge to Literary Theory.” New Literary History, vol. 2, no. 1, 1970, pp. 7–37. JSTOR, https://doi.org/10.2307/468585. Accessed 13 Nov. 2024.
  2. Foley, John Miles. “Genre(s) in the Making: Diction, Audience and Text in the Old English Seafarer.” Poetics Today, vol. 4, no. 4, 1983, pp. 683–706. JSTOR, https://doi.org/10.2307/1772320. Accessed 13 Nov. 2024.
  3. Jauss, Hans Robert, and Elizabeth Benzinger. “Literary History as a Challenge to Literary Theory.” New Literary History, vol. 2, no. 1, 1970, pp. 7–37. JSTOR, https://doi.org/10.2307/468585. Accessed 13 Nov. 2024.
  4. Mailloux, Steven. “Literary History and Reception Study.” Interpretive Conventions: The Reader in the Study of American Fiction, Cornell University Press, 1982, pp. 159–91. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.7591/j.ctt207g64r.11. Accessed 13 Nov. 2024.