“Censorship and Literature” by John Courtney Murray: Summary and Critique

“Censorship and Literature” by John Courtney Murray first appeared in The Furrow in November 1956, offering a nuanced examination of the role of censorship within both the civil and religious spheres.

"Censorship and Literature" by John Courtney Murray: Summary and Critique
Introduction: “Censorship and Literature” by John Courtney Murray

“Censorship and Literature” by John Courtney Murray first appeared in The Furrow in November 1956, offering a nuanced examination of the role of censorship within both the civil and religious spheres. Murray explores the tension between freedom of expression and societal constraints, arguing that censorship, whether governmental or non-governmental, must be a juridical process, meaning it should be structured by legal principles, rational deliberation, and public consensus. He acknowledges the necessity of some level of restriction, particularly regarding obscenity, but warns against excessive moral legislating that could undermine essential human freedoms. Central to his argument is the notion that constraints should ultimately serve freedom: “In society, constraint must be for the sake of freedom. It seems a paradox… but the constraint must create a freedom in another respect.” He critiques both libertarian and puritanical approaches to censorship, advocating instead for a pragmatic balance where restrictions are imposed only when they serve the common good without unjustly infringing on individual rights. This article remains significant in literary theory and legal discussions, as it frames censorship not as an absolute moral battle but as an intricate question of jurisprudence, prudence, and social values.

Summary of “Censorship and Literature” by John Courtney Murray

1. The Central Issue: Balancing Freedom and Restraint

  • Murray argues that the core issue of censorship revolves around striking a balance between social freedom and necessary constraints.
  • He states, “In society, constraint must be for the sake of freedom” (Murray, 1956, p. 681), suggesting that regulations should ultimately serve to increase freedom rather than diminish it.
  • He acknowledges the paradox of imposing constraints while protecting liberties and emphasizes that constraints should be minimal and justified.

2. The Role of Government in Censorship

  • He explores whether the state has the authority to impose censorship and under what conditions.
  • He notes that government censorship falls under the principle of “police power,” which extends to areas such as public morality and order (Murray, 1956, p. 680).
  • Murray warns against excessive government interference, suggesting that censorship should be limited to necessary cases that protect society without infringing on individual rights.

3. Legal Censorship vs. Moral Law

  • He differentiates between legal and moral censorship, stating, “It is not the function of the legislator to forbid everything that the moral law forbids, or to enjoin everything that the moral law enjoins” (Murray, 1956, p. 685).
  • He emphasizes that law operates on a minimal level, enforcing only the essential moral framework for social order.

4. The Problem of Censoring Sexual Morality

  • Murray highlights the challenge of regulating sexual content, noting that no government has ever successfully balanced sexual censorship without infringing on freedom or provoking negative consequences (Murray, 1956, p. 682).
  • He points out historical paradoxes, such as the severe censorship of books by the Catholic Church while prostitution was rampant in Rome (Murray, 1956, p. 683).

5. American Constitutional Approach to Freedom of Expression

  • He explains that the U.S. has constitutionally favored freedom over censorship, stating, “We have constitutionally decided that the presumption is in favor of freedom, and that the advocate of constraint must make a convincing argument for its necessity” (Murray, 1956, p. 684).
  • Prior restraint on expression is largely prohibited, with the government retaining the right to punish offenses post-publication.

6. Non-Governmental Censorship and Social Responsibility

  • Murray discusses the role of voluntary associations in censorship, distinguishing between persuasion and coercion.
  • He acknowledges the legitimacy of such organizations influencing moral standards but warns against coercive tactics like boycotts and economic pressure (Murray, 1956, p. 688-689).
  • He argues that censorship, whether governmental or private, must follow a “juridical process” guided by rationality and consensus.

7. The Role of Professional Competence in Censorship

  • He asserts that censorship should not be left to amateurs and that literary critics or experts should guide the process.
  • He references the Catholic Church’s approach, stating, “Censorship is no job for the amateur” (Murray, 1956, p. 690).
  • He warns against moral indignation overriding objective judgment in censorship decisions.

8. The “Pornography of Violence” as a Greater Concern

  • Murray argues that violent imagery combined with sexual themes is more harmful than explicit depictions of sex alone.
  • He critiques media that romanticizes violence, calling for restraint in this area (Murray, 1956, p. 691).

9. The Need for Literary Creation Over Censorship

  • He concludes by emphasizing that the focus should not be on censorship but on fostering quality literary works.
  • He cites Pope Leo XIII, who argued that “there is great danger in not reading good books” (Murray, 1956, p. 691), highlighting the need for moral and intellectual engagement rather than mere restriction.
Theoretical Terms/Concepts in “Censorship and Literature” by John Courtney Murray
Term/ConceptDefinition/ExplanationReference/Quotation
Social FreedomThe balance between individual freedom and societal constraints necessary for a functioning society.“The issue that is central in the whole problem is the issue of social freedom. More exactly, it is the issue of striking a right balance between freedom and restraint in society.” (Murray, 1956, p. 681)
Police PowerThe inherent authority of the government to regulate behaviors and enforce order for the common good.“Every government has always claimed what is called a police power, as an attribute of government.” (Murray, 1956, p. 680)
Patria PotestasThe legal principle that allows the government to act in a protective role (in loco parentis) for vulnerable individuals, such as children.“It might, if you wish, be an exercise of what is called patria potestas, the emergency power which government is entitled to use, on occasion, to protect children.” (Murray, 1956, p. 680)
Prior RestraintThe prevention of speech or publication before it occurs, often deemed unconstitutional in the U.S. legal system.“Freedom of expression is the rule, and censorship the exception. A more particular further consequence is the ban laid by the First Amendment (exceptional cases apart) on all prior restraint of communications.” (Murray, 1956, p. 684)
Juridical ProcessThe idea that censorship must be conducted through a structured legal framework, guided by fairness and rational judgment.“Censorship in the civil order must be a juridical process. In using the word ‘juridical’ I mean that the premises and objectives of the program should be defined in accord with the norms of good jurisprudence.” (Murray, 1956, p. 685)
Moral vs. Legal LawThe distinction between moral obligations and legal requirements, emphasizing that not all moral wrongs should be legally prohibited.“It is not the function of the legislator to forbid everything that the moral law forbids, or to enjoin everything that the moral law enjoins.” (Murray, 1956, p. 685)
Pluralist SocietyA society composed of diverse cultural, religious, and ideological groups, requiring a balance between majority and minority rights.“In a pluralist society no minority group has the right to demand that government should impose a general censorship, affecting all the citizenry.” (Murray, 1956, p. 687)
Voluntary CensorshipThe regulation of content by non-governmental organizations or private groups rather than the state.“There are a multitude of voluntary agencies which exercise some measure of surveillance, judgment, and even control of various media of communication.” (Murray, 1956, p. 688)
Pornography of ViolenceThe harmful combination of sexual content and violent imagery that distorts moral and ethical values.“The real evil is the violence in the impure scene. There is the perversion. If some restraint could be imposed upon this pornography of violence… it would indeed be a moral achievement.” (Murray, 1956, p. 691)
Cultural PhilistinismThe rejection or undervaluing of intellectual and artistic works due to excessive moral concerns.“It would be lamentable if Catholics were to go over to the camp of the philistines.” (Murray, 1956, p. 690)
Consensus in LawThe necessity for a shared social agreement on legal restrictions to ensure their legitimacy and effectiveness.“In the absence of this consent law either withers away or becomes tyrannical.” (Murray, 1956, p. 686)
Freedom Under LawThe principle that freedom should operate within a framework of laws that protect both individuals and society.“The freedom toward which the American people are fundamentally orientated is a freedom under God, a freedom that knows itself to be bound by the imperatives of the normal law.” (Murray, 1956, p. 684)
Contribution of “Censorship and Literature” by John Courtney Murray to Literary Theory/Theories

1. New Historicism and the Power of Institutions

  • Theory Overview: New Historicism, developed by Stephen Greenblatt, argues that literature is deeply embedded in historical and political contexts. Institutions such as the Church, the government, and the legal system play a vital role in shaping literary production and reception.
  • Murray’s Contribution:
    • He critiques the role of institutions in controlling literature, stating that censorship has historically been justified as an exercise of police power—the government’s authority to regulate public order (Murray, 1956, p. 680).
    • He acknowledges that moral constraints on literature arise from institutionalized norms but warns that these institutions must balance constraint with the promotion of freedom: “Censorship in the civil order must be a juridical process” (Murray, 1956, p. 685).
    • His discussion of the Catholic Church’s censorship of books (e.g., Index Librorum Prohibitorum) reflects New Historicist concerns about how power structures influence literary canon formation.

2. Reader-Response Theory and the Role of Interpretation

  • Theory Overview: Reader-Response Theory, led by theorists such as Wolfgang Iser and Stanley Fish, argues that the meaning of a text is shaped by the reader’s interpretation rather than by authorial intent alone.
  • Murray’s Contribution:
    • He discusses the ambiguity in defining obscenity in literature, acknowledging that different audiences will interpret texts differently: “People in general have a fairly clear notion of what obscenity is. And people in general can make, for themselves, a pretty good judgment on whether a particular work is obscene.” (Murray, 1956, p. 690).
    • His view aligns with Reader-Response Theory’s emphasis on subjective interpretation, as he argues against rigid definitions of obscenity and instead suggests that moral judgments should consider societal context.
    • By emphasizing that censorship should be guided by public consensus rather than imposed standards, Murray acknowledges the importance of the reader’s perspective in determining literary value.

3. Structuralism and the Role of Language in Censorship

  • Theory Overview: Structuralism, particularly influenced by Ferdinand de Saussure and Roland Barthes, explores how language and signs construct meaning within a cultural system.
  • Murray’s Contribution:
    • He critiques legal censorship’s reliance on arbitrary linguistic distinctions, arguing that defining literary obscenity is inherently problematic: “The Supreme Court declares that the category of the sacrilegious is altogether indefinable, while the Post Office rules that Aristophanes’ Lysistrata is an obscene book. This is indeed puzzling.” (Murray, 1956, p. 683).
    • His argument that censorship laws are textually unstable aligns with Barthes’ notion of the “death of the author”—meaning is not fixed, and different readers (or authorities) will derive different interpretations from the same text.
    • By highlighting the arbitrariness of legal and institutional linguistic frameworks, Murray indirectly supports Structuralist critiques of how meaning is socially constructed.

4. Postcolonial Theory and Cultural Hegemony

  • Theory Overview: Postcolonial theory, led by Edward Said, Homi Bhabha, and Gayatri Spivak, critiques how dominant cultures impose their values on marginalized groups through literature and censorship.
  • Murray’s Contribution:
    • He highlights the ethnocentric contradictions in Western censorship laws, questioning why certain moral and religious views dictate literature in a pluralistic society: “In a pluralist society, no minority group has the right to demand that government should impose a general censorship… according to the special standards held within one group.” (Murray, 1956, p. 687).
    • His discussion of how American and European societies differ in their definitions of obscenity reflects postcolonial concerns about how dominant cultural narratives control literature and suppress alternative voices (Murray, 1956, p. 684).
    • By advocating for diverse moral perspectives in literary regulation, he challenges hegemonic cultural norms that suppress marginalized voices.

5. Liberal Humanism and Literature’s Moral Function

  • Theory Overview: Liberal Humanism, associated with Matthew Arnold and F.R. Leavis, holds that literature’s value lies in its ability to cultivate moral and intellectual refinement.
  • Murray’s Contribution:
    • He argues that censorship should promote literary creation rather than merely restrict texts: “Our chief problem, of course, is not literary censorship, but literary creation.” (Murray, 1956, p. 691).
    • He warns against excessive focus on banning “bad” books instead of encouraging intellectual and artistic excellence: “Leo XIII is indeed remembered for his revision of the Index of Forbidden Books… But he was the first Pope to say that there is great danger in not reading good books.” (Murray, 1956, p. 691).
    • His perspective aligns with Arnold’s vision of literature as a means of cultivating higher moral and intellectual development, arguing that quality literature naturally regulates itself through aesthetic and ethical merit rather than external censorship.

6. Feminist Literary Criticism and Censorship of Sexuality

  • Theory Overview: Feminist literary criticism examines how literature represents gender, sexuality, and power dynamics.
  • Murray’s Contribution:
    • He acknowledges that literary censorship disproportionately targets works addressing sexuality, reinforcing gendered moral codes: “The strictness of traditional Catholic doctrine in regard to sexual lust appalls the libertarian; the laxness of many Catholic governments in the same regard appalls the Puritan.” (Murray, 1956, p. 683).
    • His critique of the selective censorship of sexual themes over other forms of moral corruption aligns with feminist concerns about how patriarchal institutions regulate female sexuality while permitting other social vices, such as violence.
    • He argues that censorship should prioritize addressing “pornography of violence” rather than purely sexual expression, echoing feminist calls to reconsider what constitutes harmful literature (Murray, 1956, p. 691).

Conclusion: Murray’s Multi-Theoretical Influence

Murray’s Censorship and Literature contributes to literary theory by engaging with:

  • New Historicism (institutions shaping literature),
  • Reader-Response Theory (subjective interpretation of censorship),
  • Structuralism (arbitrary definitions of obscenity),
  • Postcolonial Theory (ethnocentric censorship standards),
  • Liberal Humanism (literature’s moral role), and
  • Feminist Criticism (gendered censorship of sexuality).

His argument that censorship must balance moral concerns with literary freedom continues to inform contemporary debates about literature’s role in society.

Examples of Critiques Through “Censorship and Literature” by John Courtney Murray
Literary WorkContext of CensorshipMurray’s Argument AppliedQuotation from Censorship and Literature
James Joyce’s Ulysses (1922)Ulysses was banned for alleged obscenity, particularly for its explicit sexual references and stream-of-consciousness narration. It was declared obscene in the U.S. and U.K. before later legal victories.Murray would argue that legal censorship must be justified under juridical principles, rather than based on subjective moral outrage. He acknowledges that obscenity laws exist, but questions their application: “Law seeks to establish and maintain only that minimum of actualized morality that is necessary for the healthy functioning of the social order.” (Murray, 1956, p. 685).“It is not the function of the legislator to forbid everything that the moral law forbids.” (Murray, 1956, p. 685). He would likely critique Ulysses‘s ban as an example of overreach in legal censorship.
D.H. Lawrence’s Lady Chatterley’s Lover (1928)This novel faced bans for its explicit depictions of sex and its critique of class divisions. The U.S. and U.K. lifted the ban after trials debated the book’s literary merit.Murray’s argument about reader responsibility and subjective interpretation aligns with Lady Chatterley’s Lover‘s defense. He would likely argue that moral concerns should not automatically lead to censorship, and instead, the reader’s judgment should play a role.“People in general have a fairly clear notion of what obscenity is. And people in general can make, for themselves, a pretty good judgment on whether a particular work is obscene.” (Murray, 1956, p. 690). This aligns with the defense that Lady Chatterley’s Lover should be evaluated based on literary rather than moralistic criteria.
Salman Rushdie’s The Satanic Verses (1988)This novel was banned in several countries, and its publication led to fatwas calling for Rushdie’s execution due to its depiction of religious themes deemed blasphemous.Murray would critique the enforcement of religious censorship on a pluralistic society, emphasizing that one group’s religious beliefs should not dictate artistic freedom for all: “In a pluralist society, no minority group has the right to demand that government should impose a general censorship.” (Murray, 1956, p. 687).“No one group has the right to impose its own religious or moral views on other groups, through the use of the methods of force, coercion, or violence.” (Murray, 1956, p. 687). This applies to the violent reactions and state-imposed censorship against The Satanic Verses.
Toni Morrison’s Beloved (1987)Frequently challenged in schools for its graphic depictions of slavery, sexual violence, and trauma, critics argue that its content is inappropriate for young readers.Murray’s discussion of censorship within education suggests that while parental guidance is valid, literature should not be banned outright. He supports intellectual engagement rather than avoidance: “Our chief problem, of course, is not literary censorship, but literary creation.” (Murray, 1956, p. 691).“Certainly, the ordinary father and mother ought to be qualified to act as censors within the family… But I should not think that the ordinary father or mother, qua such, is qualified to act as censor within society at large.” (Murray, 1956, p. 690). This applies to debates on Beloved‘s place in schools—parents may limit exposure for their children but should not dictate public access.
Criticism Against “Censorship and Literature” by John Courtney Murray

1. Inconsistencies in Balancing Freedom and Restraint

  • Murray argues that freedom should be the rule and censorship the exception, yet he also justifies some forms of moral regulation (e.g., restrictions on pornography and “pornography of violence”).
  • Critics argue that this dual stance lacks clarity—who decides when censorship is justified?
  • His assertion that “constraint must be for the sake of freedom” (Murray, 1956, p. 681) is seen as contradictory since restrictions on expression inevitably limit certain freedoms.

2. Over-Reliance on Pragmatism Over Ethical Absolutism

  • Murray frames his argument through pragmatism rather than a strict ethical framework, stating that law should regulate only what is socially necessary (Murray, 1956, p. 685).
  • Some critics argue that this pragmatic approach lacks moral consistency, as it allows moral and legal relativism—what is considered obscene or harmful varies across societies.
  • His approach may justify historically oppressive censorship, such as book bans on political dissidents, under the pretext of “social necessity”.

3. Lack of Attention to Power Structures in Censorship

  • While Murray acknowledges that institutions like the Church, state, and voluntary organizations influence censorship, he does not fully critique their power dynamics.
  • New Historicist and Postcolonial critics argue that censorship is often a tool for upholding dominant ideological structures, marginalizing dissenting voices (e.g., censorship of anti-colonial literature).
  • He does not adequately address how censorship disproportionately affects marginalized communities, particularly in religious or authoritarian contexts.

4. Insufficient Engagement with Feminist and Postcolonial Criticism

  • Murray’s discussion of obscenity and morality focuses on sexual content, but he does not address how censorship historically targets feminist and postcolonial literature.
  • Feminist critics argue that censorship has long been used to silence discussions of women’s sexuality and autonomy, yet Murray largely frames the issue around moral corruption rather than gendered power structures.
  • His discussion of censorship in pluralist societies (Murray, 1956, p. 687) does not fully address how Western censorship frameworks have been imposed on non-Western cultures, particularly in colonial histories.

5. Idealistic View of Public Consensus and Legal Enforcement

  • Murray claims that censorship should be guided by public consensus: “No society should expect very much in the way of moral uplift from its censorship statutes.” (Murray, 1956, p. 685).
  • Critics argue that this overestimates the fairness of democratic consensus, as majority rule can still suppress minority voices.
  • He does not fully address who gets to shape public consensus—powerful elites, religious institutions, or legal authorities?

6. Overemphasis on Religious Morality in Censorship Debates

  • While Murray argues for pluralism, he still leans heavily on Catholic moral philosophy, using Christian ethical reasoning to justify certain censorship principles.
  • His emphasis on moral constraints in literature (Murray, 1956, p. 690) suggests a preference for religious moral frameworks, which some critics view as exclusionary in secular or multi-faith societies.
  • Secular critics argue that censorship debates should be guided by human rights principles rather than religious morality.

7. Failure to Address the Role of Economic and Corporate Censorship

  • Murray primarily focuses on governmental and voluntary censorship but does not discuss corporate censorship, where publishers, media companies, and private entities restrict literature based on commercial interests.
  • In the modern era, corporate media often suppresses politically controversial works—a major oversight in Murray’s framework.
  • His legalistic focus on state censorship does not address how economic power structures influence what literature gets published and distributed.
Representative Quotations from “Censorship and Literature” by John Courtney Murray with Explanation
QuotationExplanation
“First, in society constraint must be for the sake of freedom.” (p. 681)Murray argues that restrictions on freedom should be justified only if they lead to greater overall freedom. This paradox suggests that certain limitations, such as traffic laws, ultimately enable freer movement rather than inhibit it.
“Every constraint has multiple effects; it may impose restraints on a freedom which you would wish to see untouched.” (p. 682)He highlights the unintended consequences of censorship, suggesting that regulating one type of expression could limit another vital freedom, such as political speech.
“We have constitutionally decided that the presumption is in favour of freedom, and that the advocate of constraint must make a convincing argument for its necessity or utility in the particular case.” (p. 684)Murray acknowledges that the American legal system favors free speech, placing the burden of proof on those advocating censorship rather than on those defending freedom of expression.
“Law seeks to establish and maintain only that minimum of actualized morality that is necessary for the healthy functioning of the social order.” (p. 685)He differentiates between moral law and legal restrictions, arguing that law should enforce only the essential moral standards required to maintain social order, rather than all ethical norms.
“Good laws are obeyed by the generality because they are good laws; they merit and receive the consent of the community.” (p. 686)This emphasizes the importance of public consensus in legal enforcement, suggesting that laws lacking societal support risk becoming oppressive rather than effective.
“Each minority group has the right to censor for its own members, if it so chooses, the content of the various media of communication.” (p. 687)Murray recognizes the right of private groups (such as religious communities) to impose self-censorship but warns against extending those standards to the entire society.
“The censor is not called upon for a display of moral indignation; he is asked only for a judgment, calm and cool, objective and unemotional.” (p. 690)He outlines ideal principles for censorship, arguing that decisions should be based on rational legal principles rather than personal or emotional reactions.
“If adult standards of literature would be dangerous for children, a child’s standard of literature is rather appalling to an adult.” (p. 691)Murray critiques overprotective censorship, arguing that society should not be bound by children’s moral standards, which would drastically limit adult literary freedom.
“Few things are worse than to make oneself ridiculous. And when an effort to coerce is made at the dictates of stupidity, the result arouses ridicule as well as resentment.” (p. 689)This statement satirizes overzealous censorship efforts, suggesting that they often fail because they lack intelligence and proportionality.
“Our chief problem, of course, is not literary censorship, but literary creation.” (p. 691)In his conclusion, Murray shifts the focus from censorship to the need for high-quality literature, suggesting that the real issue is not suppressing bad books but fostering great ones.
Suggested Readings: “Censorship and Literature” by John Courtney Murray
  1. Murray, John Courtney. “Censorship and Literature.” The Furrow, vol. 7, no. 11, 1956, pp. 679–91. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/27657052. Accessed 2 Feb. 2025.
  2. Coffin, Victor. “Censorship and Literature Under Napoleon I.” The American Historical Review, vol. 22, no. 2, 1917, pp. 288–308. JSTOR, https://doi.org/10.2307/1834962. Accessed 2 Feb. 2025.
  3. Cressy, David. “Book Burning in Tudor and Stuart England.” The Sixteenth Century Journal, vol. 36, no. 2, 2005, pp. 359–74. JSTOR, https://doi.org/10.2307/20477359. Accessed 2 Feb. 2025.
  4. Henricksen, Bruce, and Michael Holquist. “The Paradox of Censorship.” PMLA, vol. 109, no. 3, 1994, pp. 443–45. JSTOR, https://doi.org/10.2307/463082. Accessed 2 Feb. 2025.

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *