Introduction: âHow Ordinary Is Ordinary Language?â by Stanley E. Fish
âHow Ordinary Is Ordinary Language?â by Stanley E. Fish first appeared in 1973 in the New Literary History journal. This essay is considered a pivotal piece in the development of New Criticism and reader-response theory. Fish argues that language is not merely a neutral tool for conveying meaning but is actively shaped by the readerâs interpretive strategies. This idea challenges traditional notions of authorial intent and objective meaning, emphasizing the subjective nature of literary interpretation. Fishâs essay has had a significant impact on literary theory, influencing discussions about the relationship between the text, the reader, and the cultural context.
Summary of âHow Ordinary Is Ordinary Language?â by Stanley E. Fish
- Linguistics and Literary Criticism: A Lingering Debate Fish begins by addressing the long-standing conflict between linguists and literary critics, a debate ongoing for over 20 years. Linguists assert that literature is fundamentally language and therefore, linguistic analysis is relevant. In contrast, critics argue that linguistic analyses miss essential elements of literature, particularly what makes it unique (âlinguists have failed to distinguish clearly between the structure of language and the structure of literatureâ â p. 43). This mutual critique has led to a stalemate in reconciling the two fields.
- The Misconception of Ordinary Language Fish highlights that both linguists and critics err by assuming a distinction between ordinary and literary language. This split trivializes both, as ordinary language is stripped of its human values, purpose, and context, reducing it to mere form (âthe very act of distinguishing between ordinary and literary language, because of what it assumes, leads necessarily to an inadequate account of bothâ â p. 45). Fish contends that separating ordinary and literary language impoverishes our understanding of both domains.
- Trivialization of Ordinary Language By excluding purpose, value, and intention from ordinary language, it becomes sterile, a mere system devoid of human essence. Literature, then, is relegated to a marginal status where its deviation from this impoverished language is seen as inferior or parasitic (Fish critiques this as âdeviation theories always trivialize the norm and therefore trivialize everything elseâ â p. 44). This binary approach reduces the value of both language and literature, imposing artificial constraints on their interpretation.
- The Failure of Deviation Theories Fish critiques what he terms âdeviation theories,â which separate ordinary and literary language by designating literary language as a deviation from the norm. This categorization, according to Fish, trivializes both the norm (ordinary language) and what deviates from it (literary language). The consequence is a diminished understanding of the richness inherent in both language forms.
- Restoring Value to Ordinary Language Fish argues for a new perspective that restores human content to language, rejecting the trivializing effect of treating language as a formal system without values. He draws on speech act theory and philosophical semantics to propose that ordinary language, far from being devoid of human values, is deeply infused with them. This approach offers a way to view literature not as a deviation but as an enriched form of language, full of human purpose and intention (âa theory which restores human content to language also restores legitimate status to literatureâ â p. 50).
- Implications for Linguistics and Literary Theory Fish suggests that embracing the human and intentional aspects of ordinary language opens up possibilities for new methods of literary analysis. Literature is no longer a special category isolated from everyday discourse but an integral part of language, shaped by the same values and purposes that govern human communication (âwhat characterizes literature is not formal properties, but an attitudeâalways within our power to assumeâtoward properties that belong by constitutive right to languageâ â p. 52).
- Conclusion: Literature as Framed Language Ultimately, Fish concludes that literature is distinguished not by its inherent linguistic features but by the frame we impose on it, signaling our intent to examine language with heightened awareness (âliterature is language around which we have drawn a frame, a frame that indicates a decision to regard with a particular self-consciousness the resources language has always possessedâ â p. 52). This redefinition collapses the binary distinction between ordinary and literary language, positioning both as part of a continuum rather than separate entities.
Literary Terms/Concepts in âHow Ordinary Is Ordinary Language?â by Stanley E. Fish
Term/Concept | Explanation |
Ordinary Language | Refers to language as it is used in everyday communication, often contrasted with literary language. Fish critiques its reduction to a formal system devoid of human values. |
Literary Language | The language used in literature, often seen as distinct from ordinary language. Fish challenges the notion that literary language deviates from ordinary language. |
Deviation Theory | The idea that literary language is a deviation from the norm of ordinary language. Fish argues that this trivializes both types of language. |
Speech Act Theory | A philosophical theory (rooted in the work of J.L. Austin and John Searle) that sees utterances as actions rather than mere statements. Fish uses this theory to argue that all language is permeated with human intention and purpose. |
Formalism | An approach to literary theory that emphasizes the form or structure of a text over its content or meaning. Fish critiques this focus on form as limiting the understanding of language and literature. |
Message-Plus Theory | A theory of literature that sees literary texts as conveying messages more effectively or beautifully than ordinary language. Fish criticizes this as prioritizing style over content. |
Message-Minus Theory | A view of literature that emphasizes style and form, often at the expense of content or message. Fish sees this as equally limiting. |
Positivism | A belief in objective, observable facts that underpin both linguistic and literary analysis. Fish critiques this as ignoring the human values embedded in language. |
Performative Language | Language that accomplishes an action (e.g., promising, ordering) rather than merely describing something. Fish references this concept to argue that all language, including ordinary language, is performative. |
Norm | The idea of a standard or conventional form of language (ordinary language). Fish argues that deviation theories establish a norm that diminishes both ordinary and literary language. |
Framing | The act of drawing attention to language by framing it in a particular way, often seen in literature. Fish argues that literature is distinguished by the frame we impose around language, not by inherent linguistic properties. |
Autonomy of Criticism | The idea that literary criticism operates independently from other disciplines, like linguistics. Fish critiques this separation as artificial and unproductive. |
Contribution of âHow Ordinary Is Ordinary Language?â by Stanley E. Fish to Literary Theory/Theories
1. Challenge to Formalism
- Contribution: Fish critiques formalism, which emphasizes the structure and form of literary texts over content. He argues that formalist approaches to literature fail to capture the richness of both ordinary and literary language.
- Quotation: Fish states that âthe very act of distinguishing between ordinary and literary language⊠leads necessarily to an inadequate account of bothâ (p. 45). He suggests that formalism trivializes both the norm of ordinary language and the deviation that defines literature in formalist terms.
2. Critique of Structuralism
- Contribution: Fish indirectly critiques structuralism, especially the structuralist emphasis on the underlying structures of language. He opposes the view that literary language is a formal deviation from an ordinary linguistic structure.
- Quotation: Fish critiques Roman Jakobsonâs structuralist approach, noting that in Jakobsonâs view, âthe chief task of literary theory is to discover âwhat makes a verbal message a work of art'â, and that this method implies âa verbal messageâ is something distinct from language itself (p. 48).
3. Expansion of Speech Act Theory in Literary Studies
- Contribution: Fish applies Speech Act Theory to literary criticism, arguing that all languageâordinary or literaryâcarries human intention, purpose, and value. This suggests that literature should be analyzed as a form of human action rather than as a distinct language form.
- Quotation: Fish argues, âthe strongest contention of the theory [speech act theory] is that all utterances are to be so regarded [as speech acts], and the importance of that contention is⊠âwhat we have to study is not the sentence⊠but the issuing of an utterance in a situationâ by a human beingâ (p. 50-51).
4. Rejection of the Ordinary vs. Literary Language Distinction
- Contribution: Fish challenges the ordinary vs. literary language dichotomy by asserting that all language is inherently rich in purpose and human values. He calls for a unified approach to analyzing all forms of language, rejecting the idea that literary language is a deviation from an ordinary linguistic norm.
- Quotation: Fish criticizes this division, stating, âIt is my contention that the very act of distinguishing between ordinary and literary language⊠leads to an inadequate account of bothâ (p. 45). He argues that âordinary language is extraordinary because at its heart is⊠the realm of values, intentions, and purposesâ (p. 51).
5. Contribution to Reader-Response Theory
- Contribution: Fishâs notion of âframingâ language aligns with reader-response theory, where the meaning of a text emerges through the interaction between the reader and the text. He argues that literature is not defined by its language but by the attitude or âframeâ that readers impose on it.
- Quotation: Fish asserts that âwhat characterizes literature⊠is not formal properties, but an attitudeâalways within our power to assumeâtoward properties that belong by constitutive right to languageâ (p. 52). This notion reflects the idea that the readerâs role in interpreting a text is central to its literary value.
6. Critique of Positivism in Literary and Linguistic Theory
- Contribution: Fish critiques positivism, the belief that language can be understood purely through formal, objective analysis. He argues that this approach strips language of its human essence and results in an artificial separation between language and literature.
- Quotation: Fish criticizes âthe positivist assumption that ordinary language is available to a purely formal descriptionâ, noting that this assumption impoverishes our understanding of both language and literature (p. 44).
7. Reevaluation of Literary Value and Aesthetic Judgment
- Contribution: Fishâs argument leads to a reevaluation of how literary value and aesthetic judgment are determined. He claims that the evaluative criteria used to identify literature are not universal, but local and context-specific, reflecting collective decisions about what counts as literature.
- Quotation: He argues that âcriteria of evaluation (that is, criteria for identifying literature) are valid only for the aesthetic they support and reflectâ, and that âall aesthetics⊠are local and conventional rather than universalâ (p. 53).
8. Impact on Deconstruction
- Contribution: While Fish doesnât directly engage with deconstruction, his rejection of fixed linguistic boundaries between literary and ordinary language prefigures deconstructionist ideas, particularly the notion that meaning is fluid and constructed by both the text and its interpretation.
- Quotation: Fish notes that âliterature is no longer granted a special statusâ, which suggests a leveling of all types of language as valid sites for meaning-making (p. 52).
Examples of Critiques Through âHow Ordinary Is Ordinary Language?â by Stanley E. Fish
Literary Work | Traditional Critique | Critique Using Fishâs Framework |
âA Modest Proposalâ by Jonathan Swift | Typically analyzed for its satirical content and use of irony, showing how Swift criticizes British policies toward Ireland through exaggerated, grotesque proposals. | Fishâs critique would focus on how the human intentions and values embedded in Swiftâs language are inseparable from its ordinary usage. The satire becomes powerful because it uses âordinaryâ language for extraordinary human critique, uniting purpose, values, and intentions with the language itself. |
âUlyssesâ by James Joyce | Often analyzed through formalistic or structuralist lenses, focusing on Joyceâs complex narrative techniques and stream-of-consciousness writing style. | Fish would argue against viewing Joyceâs language as a deviation from the norm. Instead, he would suggest that Joyceâs language is an example of how ordinary language is extraordinary in conveying deeply human experiences, like consciousness and memory. Joyceâs form and content are unified by purpose and value. |
âThe Faerie Queeneâ by Edmund Spenser | Traditionally critiqued for its allegorical content and use of archaic language, often analyzed for the moral and religious messages encoded in its elaborate structure. | Fish might critique the tendency to regard Spenserâs work as formally difficult or deviational. He would emphasize that Spenserâs language reflects the human purposes and values at play in his moral allegory, and that understanding these values unites the language and meaning without seeing the language as distinct from the human content. |
âThe Waste Landâ by T.S. Eliot | Seen through a Modernist lens, it is typically critiqued for its fragmentary structure and allusions to classical and contemporary texts, representing a fragmented modern consciousness. | Rather than focusing on the fragmentation as a formal deviation, Fishâs critique would emphasize how Eliotâs ordinary language reflects extraordinary human concerns about alienation and despair. He would argue that Eliotâs style is not a departure from ordinary language but is deeply tied to expressing human experience in modernity. |
âHow Do I Love Theeâ by Elizabeth Barrett Browning | Frequently analyzed as a romantic love poem, it is traditionally viewed through its emotional expressiveness and its adherence to sonnet form. | Fish would challenge the notion that lyric poetry such as this can be separated from ordinary language. He might focus on how Browningâs poem uses language imbued with purpose and intention, making it part of the continuum of everyday communication rather than a deviation. The poetic language and emotional expression are united with ordinary human values. |
âAn Essay on Manâ by Alexander Pope | Critiqued for its didactic tone and focus on philosophical arguments about human nature, often seen as a blend of poetry and rational discourse. | Fish would reject the idea that Popeâs rational arguments reduce the workâs literary status. He would argue that the values and purposes in Popeâs writing (exploring human existence) are inseparable from the language, demonstrating that ordinary and literary language are united by human intention. |
âThe Rape of the Lockâ by Alexander Pope | Analyzed as a mock-epic, it uses the grand style of classical epics to satirize trivial contemporary events, particularly in social satire. | Fish would critique how this satirical work demonstrates that ordinary language is inherently literary. The high and low elements are both part of a unified language that serves human purposesâhere, satirical and moral commentary. The workâs playfulness with form does not separate it from ordinary language but exemplifies how all language is embedded with purpose. |
Criticism Against âHow Ordinary Is Ordinary Language?â by Stanley E. Fish
- Oversimplification of Literary-Linguistic Distinctions
Critics might argue that Fish oversimplifies the established distinction between literary and ordinary language. By collapsing the two categories, he potentially overlooks important formal, structural, and stylistic differences that distinguish literary works from everyday speech. - Neglect of Formalismâs Contributions
Fishâs critique of formalism can be seen as dismissive of the valuable insights that formal analysis provides. Formalist approaches allow for a deep understanding of the technical elements that contribute to a textâs meaning, and Fishâs rejection might be viewed as undermining this aspect of literary scholarship. - Undervaluing the Role of Aesthetic Experience
Some critics could claim that Fish diminishes the aesthetic value of literature by focusing too heavily on its embedded human purposes and intentions. By merging literary and ordinary language, Fish may downplay the unique aesthetic experiences that literature offers, which are often central to its value. - Ambiguity in the âFramingâ Concept
Fishâs idea that literature is created through the âframeâ readers impose on language has been critiqued as vague and subjective. Critics argue that it is unclear how this framing process operates, and it leaves too much open to interpretation, making it difficult to apply consistently across literary criticism. - Overreliance on Reader-Response Theory
Fishâs emphasis on the readerâs role in making language âliteraryâ aligns with reader-response theory, but some scholars criticize this approach for giving too much agency to the reader. This focus potentially neglects the textâs inherent qualities and undermines the importance of authorial intention. - Failure to Address the Practical Limits of Linguistics in Literary Criticism
While Fish critiques linguistic approaches for failing to account for human purposes in language, critics may argue that Fish does not fully address the practical limitations of using linguistics as a tool for literary criticism. Linguistics, as a discipline, might not be designed to capture the aesthetic and symbolic dimensions of literary works. - Challenges to the Elimination of Literary Status
Fishâs assertion that literature does not hold a special status might be criticized for eroding the distinctive cultural and intellectual value that has traditionally been afforded to literary works. This claim could be seen as reducing literatureâs unique role in society by merging it too closely with ordinary language. - Resistance from Structuralist and Post-Structuralist Thinkers
Structuralist and post-structuralist theorists might argue that Fishâs rejection of linguistic structures in favor of human intentions overlooks the importance of deeper linguistic patterns and structures that underlie both ordinary and literary language. Fishâs approach may seem too focused on external human contexts rather than internal textual structures. - Limited Applicability Across Genres
Some critics might argue that Fishâs theory does not account for the diversity of literary genres. For example, works of experimental fiction or poetry that deliberately play with language in non-ordinary ways may not fit comfortably within Fishâs unified framework of language.
Representative Quotations from âHow Ordinary Is Ordinary Language?â by Stanley E. Fish with Explanation
- âDeviation theories always trivialize the norm and therefore trivialize everything else.â
Fish critiques the common distinction between ordinary and literary language, arguing that categorizing literary language as a deviation from the norm reduces the significance of both ordinary and literary language (p. 44). - âThe task of the linguist⊠is limited to describing those formal components of a literary text which are accessible to him, but the linguist cannot judge the value of these various features; only the literary critic can do that.â
Fish references the linguistâs constrained role in literary criticism, critiquing the positivist assumption that linguistic analysis can exclude value judgments, which are essential for literary studies (p. 45). - âOrdinary language is extraordinary because at its heart is precisely that realm of values, intentions, and purposes which is often assumed to be the exclusive property of literature.â
Fish argues that ordinary language is not a neutral medium but is deeply intertwined with human purpose, making it as complex and value-laden as literary language (p. 51). - âWhat characterizes literature then is not formal properties, but an attitudeâalways within our power to assumeâtoward properties that belong by constitutive right to language.â
Fish challenges formalist approaches to defining literature by arguing that literature is defined by the readerâs frame of mind, not by intrinsic formal properties (p. 52). - âThe very act of distinguishing between ordinary and literary language, because of what it assumes, leads necessarily to an inadequate account of both.â
Fish asserts that creating a dichotomy between ordinary and literary language results in an impoverished understanding of each, as both are interwoven with human values and intentions (p. 45). - âBy accepting the positivist assumption that ordinary language is available to a purely formal description, both sides assure that their investigations of literary language will be fruitless and arid.â
Fish critiques the positivist notion that ordinary language can be analyzed purely through form, without considering its human content. This leads, he argues, to an incomplete understanding of literary language as well (p. 44). - âCriticism, in its present form, is forced to choose between separating literature from life or reintegrating it with the impoverished notion of life implicit in the norm of ordinary language.â
Fish identifies a central problem in contemporary criticism: either treat literature as separate from life or reintegrate it with a shallow understanding of ordinary language (p. 48). - âIn short, what philosophical semantics and the philosophy of speech acts are telling us is that ordinary language is extraordinary.â
Drawing on speech act theory, Fish argues that all language is imbued with human purpose and meaning, collapsing the distinction between ordinary and literary language (p. 51). - âA theory which restores human content to language also restores legitimate status to literature by reuniting it with a norm that is no longer trivialized.â
Fish suggests that if we view ordinary language as rich with human content, literature too can be seen as part of this continuity, rather than as something deviant or lesser (p. 51). - âAll aesthetics⊠are local and conventional rather than universal, reflecting a collective decision as to what will count as literature.â
Fish challenges universal aesthetic standards, arguing that judgments about what constitutes literature are culturally constructed and subject to change (p. 53).
Suggested Readings: âHow Ordinary Is Ordinary Language?â by Stanley E. Fish
- Austin, J. L. How to Do Things with Words. Oxford University Press, 1962.
- Searle, John R. Speech Acts: An Essay in the Philosophy of Language. Cambridge University Press, 1969.
- Jakobson, Roman. âClosing Statement: Linguistics and Poetics.â Style in Language, edited by Thomas A. Sebeok, MIT Press, 1960, pp. 350â377. https://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/9780262010550.003.0029
- Ohmann, Richard. âSpeech Acts and the Definition of Literature.â Philosophy and Rhetoric, vol. 4, no. 1, 1971, pp. 1â19.
URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/40236802 - Barthes, Roland. Writing Degree Zero. Translated by Annette Lavers and Colin Smith, Hill and Wang, 1967.
- Fowler, Roger. Linguistics and the Novel. Methuen, 1977.