“In Defence Of Overinterpretation” by Jonathan Culler: Summary and Critique

“In Defence of Overinterpretation” by Jonathan Culler first appeared in 1992 as part of the volume Interpretation and Overinterpretation, edited by Stefan Collini and published by Cambridge University Press.

"In Defence Of Overinterpretation" by Jonathan Culler: Summary and Critique
Introduction: “In Defence Of Overinterpretation” by Jonathan Culler

“In Defence of Overinterpretation” by Jonathan Culler first appeared in 1992 as part of the volume Interpretation and Overinterpretation, edited by Stefan Collini and published by Cambridge University Press. The essay critically engages with Umberto Eco’s lectures on the boundaries of interpretation and Richard Rorty’s commentary, offering a robust defence of “overinterpretation” as a valuable intellectual exercise. Culler argues that interpretation becomes meaningful and insightful when it pushes beyond moderation and conventional readings, often uncovering previously unnoticed connections and implications within a text. He introduces the idea of “overstanding” (a term borrowed from Wayne Booth), which entails asking questions that a text does not directly invite, thereby deepening our understanding of literature and its broader cultural and semiotic mechanisms. Culler’s work is significant in literary theory as it challenges the limits imposed by moderate interpretation and defends the role of critical inquiry, even when it risks being labeled excessive. By advocating for rigorous and imaginative readings, Culler underscores the importance of interpretation in revealing the dynamic and often ambiguous interplay of meaning in literary texts, thus fostering continued intellectual engagement with literature.

Summary of “In Defence Of Overinterpretation” by Jonathan Culler
  • Introduction and Context
    Jonathan Culler’s essay “In Defence of Overinterpretation” appeared in the volume Interpretation and Overinterpretation (1992), edited by Stefan Collini. It responds to Umberto Eco’s lectures on the limits of interpretation and Richard Rorty’s critique. Culler defends “overinterpretation” as a legitimate and productive aspect of literary criticism, rejecting simplistic pragmatist positions that dismiss critical inquiry into texts’ structures and functions (Culler, 1992).
  • Extreme Interpretations vs. Moderate Interpretations
    Culler argues that interpretation gains intellectual value when it is “extreme,” rather than moderate. While consensus-driven interpretations may have merit, they lack the potential to uncover new insights or connections. He states, “if critics are going to spend their time working out and proposing interpretations, then they should apply as much interpretive pressure as they can” (Culler, 1992, p. 110).
  • Eco’s Lectures and Rossetti’s Dante Interpretation
    Culler critiques Eco’s examples of “overinterpretation” and clarifies that certain flawed interpretations, like Rossetti’s Rosicrucian analysis of Dante, are instances of underinterpretation rather than overextension. Rossetti failed to sufficiently interpret all textual elements or establish valid connections (Culler, 1992, p. 111).
  • Defending Overstanding
    Culler borrows Wayne Booth’s concept of “overstanding,” which entails asking questions that the text does not explicitly encourage. Such inquiries — for example, analyzing the ideological or cultural implications of stories like The Three Little Pigs — can reveal latent meanings or overlooked structures (Culler, 1992, p. 113).
  • Criticism of Pragmatist Views (Rorty)
    Culler critiques Richard Rorty’s pragmatist stance, which reduces all textual engagement to “use.” Rorty suggests we abandon structural analysis and “simply enjoy” texts, much like using software without understanding its code. Culler counters that academic inquiry into how texts function is essential, just as linguistics studies language systems (Culler, 1992, p. 117).
  • The Role of Deconstruction
    Addressing Eco and Rorty’s shared dismissal of deconstruction, Culler clarifies that deconstruction reveals textual structures and undermines rigid limits to meaning. It demonstrates that meaning is context-dependent and endlessly generative, not a reader’s arbitrary creation (Culler, 1992, p. 120).
  • Overinterpretation as Discovery
    Culler embraces the “excess of wonder” that comes with overinterpretation, defending it as a vital tool for literary criticism. He invokes Roland Barthes’ idea that systematic re-reading and puzzling over textual elements often lead to discoveries about the text and the systems enabling meaning production (Culler, 1992, p. 122).
Theoretical Terms/Concepts in “In Defence Of Overinterpretation” by Jonathan Culler
Theoretical Term/ConceptDefinition/DescriptionRole in Culler’s Argument
OverinterpretationAn interpretative practice that pushes beyond consensus and explores unconventional meanings in a text.Culler defends overinterpretation as intellectually valuable, fostering discoveries about texts and systems.
Moderate InterpretationInterpretations that align with established readings and consensus, often lacking new insights.Criticized for being uninteresting and failing to push interpretive boundaries.
Extreme InterpretationInterpretations that challenge norms and apply maximum interpretive pressure to reveal new connections.Praised for its ability to generate insights and uncover hidden implications.
OverstandingA concept introduced by Wayne Booth, referring to asking questions the text does not explicitly encourage.Used to support the importance of asking unconventional, critical questions about texts.
PragmatismA philosophical approach (espoused by Rorty) that advocates practical use of texts rather than understanding their structures.Critiqued as reductive, as it dismisses structural understanding in favor of practical “use.”
Model ReaderUmberto Eco’s idea of the ideal reader who asks the questions a text inherently suggests.Represents Eco’s boundary for “proper” interpretation, which Culler challenges.
Paranoid InterpretationAn interpretative approach where insignificant elements are excessively analyzed for hidden meanings.Linked to Eco’s criticism; Culler acknowledges its role but defends paranoia as sometimes productive.
DeconstructionA critical approach that reveals textual structures and undermines rigid categories of meaning.Clarifies its role as exploring textual structures and their disruptions in meaning.
Excess of WonderA state of curiosity or wonder that motivates critics to explore even seemingly trivial elements in texts.Advocated as a positive trait, encouraging critical inquiry and exploration.
SemioticsThe study of signs, codes, and systems of meaning, central to understanding how texts generate meaning.Highlighted as a crucial method for understanding how meaning is produced in literature.
Contribution of “In Defence Of Overinterpretation” by Jonathan Culler to Literary Theory/Theories
  1. Defence of Overinterpretation as Intellectual Exploration
    • Culler argues that extreme interpretations push the boundaries of textual meaning, revealing connections and implications that moderate readings might miss. This stance challenges the traditional limits of interpretative theory.
    • “Interpretation itself needs no defence… but like most intellectual activities, interpretation is interesting only when it is extreme” (Culler, 1992, p. 110).
  2. Challenging Eco’s Limits of Interpretation
    • Culler critiques Umberto Eco’s model of a “sound” interpretation and pushes back against Eco’s dismissal of extreme readings, suggesting that overinterpretation uncovers textual complexities and cultural implications.
    • “The idea of ‘overinterpretation’… fails to capture the problems Professor Eco himself wishes to address” (Culler, 1992, p. 111).
  3. Introduction of Booth’s Overstanding
    • Culler incorporates Wayne Booth’s concept of “overstanding,” where critics ask questions the text does not explicitly pose. This expands literary theory by valuing inquiries about ideology, culture, and suppressed meanings.
    • “Overstanding… consists of pursuing questions that the text does not pose to its model reader” (Culler, 1992, p. 113).
  4. Critique of Pragmatism and Rorty’s ‘Use’ Theory
    • Culler challenges Richard Rorty’s pragmatist claim that texts should merely be used for practical purposes. He insists that literary studies require an analysis of how texts function structurally and semiotically.
    • “To tell people they should give up attempting to identify underlying structures… is to attempt to block other people from doing work” (Culler, 1992, p. 118).
  5. Reaffirming Deconstruction’s Role
    • Culler clarifies the contribution of deconstruction, which emphasizes the endless generation of meaning and challenges fixed interpretive limits. This reaffirms deconstruction’s value in literary theory.
    • “Deconstruction… stresses that meaning is context bound… but that context itself is boundless” (Culler, 1992, p. 120).
  6. Highlighting Semiotics as Critical Inquiry
    • Culler underscores semiotics (the science of signs) as central to literary theory, advocating for the analysis of meaning-making systems within texts and broader cultural practices.
    • “Semiotics… is precisely the attempt to identify the codes and mechanisms through which meaning is produced” (Culler, 1992, p. 116).
  7. Rejection of Moderate Criticism in Favor of Textual Pressure
    • By advocating for interpretive extremes, Culler contributes to literary theories that value intellectual risk and deep inquiry, rejecting consensus-driven, moderate criticism.
    • “If critics… propose interpretations, then they should apply as much interpretive pressure as they can” (Culler, 1992, p. 110).
  8. Rediscovery of Wonder in Interpretation
    • Culler promotes the “excess of wonder” in literary analysis, encouraging critics to puzzle over seemingly insignificant elements of texts as a pathway to deeper understanding.
    • “This deformation professionnelle… seems to me the best source of insights into language and literature that we seek” (Culler, 1992, p. 122).
Examples of Critiques Through “In Defence Of Overinterpretation” by Jonathan Culler
Literary WorkInterpretation ExampleCuller’s Position
Dante’s Divine Comedy (Rossetti’s Interpretation)Rossetti attempted to impose a Rosicrucian thematic on the poem by drawing from unrelated motifs, such as the pelican, which rarely appear. The failure lies in underinterpretation, not overinterpretation.Culler argues this is a failure of interpretation as Rossetti neglected crucial elements and failed to connect them convincingly (Culler, 1992, p. 111).
Wordsworth’s A Slumber Did My Spirit SealGeoffrey Hartman interprets diurnal as evoking a funeral motif and suggests echoes of tears through rhyming words like fears and years. Culler defends the value of extending such readings further.Culler asserts that pushing such interpretations further might illuminate hidden meanings, even if ultimately rejected (Culler, 1992, p. 112).
The Three Little Pigs (Folk Tale)Wayne Booth proposes asking unconventional questions like cultural implications, unconscious dreams, or triadic patterns. These questions move beyond surface interpretation into overstanding.Culler supports overstanding as a way to generate insights into ideological, cultural, and historical dimensions of a text (Culler, 1992, p. 113).
Casual Greeting “Lovely Day, Isn’t It?”Eco criticizes paranoid interpretations of casual phrases. Culler defends the exploration of why such phrases exist culturally and socially, highlighting hidden systems of communication.Culler emphasizes that overinterpretation of such phrases reflects cultural functions and mechanisms worth analyzing (Culler, 1992, p. 115).
Criticism Against “In Defence Of Overinterpretation” by Jonathan Culler
  1. Ambiguity of Overinterpretation
    • Critics argue that Culler does not clearly define where overinterpretation becomes unproductive or nonsensical. The boundary between valuable inquiry and frivolous excess remains blurred.
  2. Neglect of Authorial Intention
    • Culler’s defense of extreme interpretations sidelines the importance of authorial intention, which remains central to traditional literary studies and reader-focused approaches.
  3. Overreliance on Overstanding
    • While Culler praises Wayne Booth’s concept of “overstanding,” critics argue that asking questions the text does not propose risks irrelevance and distracts from the text’s inherent meanings.
  4. Dismissal of Moderate Interpretation
    • Culler’s critique of moderate interpretations as “uninteresting” is seen as overly dismissive. Moderate readings often establish foundational understandings necessary for deeper inquiry.
  5. Potential for Misreading
    • By advocating for interpretative extremes, Culler risks encouraging arbitrary or misguided readings that may distort rather than illuminate the text.
  6. Undermining Pragmatism’s Practicality
    • Critics of Culler suggest that his rejection of Richard Rorty’s pragmatic approach overlooks the practical value of engaging with texts for immediate understanding rather than academic analysis.
  7. Lack of Clear Methodology
    • Culler’s argument for “interpretive pressure” lacks a structured method for applying overinterpretation effectively, leaving its application open-ended and subjective.
  8. Excessive Emphasis on Semiotics
    • While semiotics plays a central role in Culler’s argument, critics claim it prioritizes theoretical frameworks over the literary experience, potentially alienating readers and scholars less inclined to theoretical analysis.
  9. Risk of Paranoia in Interpretation
    • Culler’s defense of paranoid or excessive interpretation risks legitimizing unsubstantiated claims, creating unnecessary complexity in literary studies.
Representative Quotations from “In Defence Of Overinterpretation” by Jonathan Culler with Explanation
QuotationExplanation
1. “Interpretation itself needs no defence; it is with us always, but like most intellectual activities, interpretation is interesting only when it is extreme.” (Culler, 1992, p. 110)Culler argues that interpretations gain significance when they challenge conventions and push intellectual boundaries rather than remain moderate or predictable.
2. “Moderate interpretation, which articulates a consensus, though it may have value in some circumstances, is of little interest.” (Culler, 1992, p. 110)This highlights Culler’s critique of consensus-driven interpretations, which fail to reveal new insights or push interpretive thinking forward.
3. “If critics are going to spend their time working out and proposing interpretations, then they should apply as much interpretive pressure as they can, should carry their thinking as far as it can go.” (Culler, 1992, p. 110)Culler calls for rigorous, extreme interpretations to uncover deeper, previously unnoticed meanings in literary texts.
4. “Overinterpretation may in fact be a practice of asking precisely those questions which are not necessary for normal communication but which enable us to reflect on its functioning.” (Culler, 1992, p. 115)Overinterpretation, according to Culler, serves as a critical tool to interrogate the cultural and linguistic mechanisms underlying seemingly simple textual elements.
5. “One advantage of Booth’s opposition over Eco’s is that it makes it easier to see the role and importance of overstanding than when this sort of practice is tendentiously called overinterpretation.” (Culler, 1992, p. 113)Culler prefers Booth’s concept of “overstanding” as a positive critical practice that explores questions outside the text’s immediate scope.
6. “To tell people they should give up attempting to identify underlying structures and systems but just use texts for their own purposes is to attempt to block other people from doing work like that for which he gained recognition.” (Culler, 1992, p. 118)Culler criticizes Rorty’s pragmatist view, arguing that abandoning structural analysis limits scholarly exploration and critical knowledge.
7. “Deconstruction, on the contrary, stresses that meaning is context bound – a function of relations within or between texts – but that context itself is boundless.” (Culler, 1992, p. 120)Culler defends deconstruction, emphasizing its focus on the endless contextual possibilities of meaning-making in texts.
8. “It would be sad indeed if fear of ‘overinterpretation’ should lead us to avoid or repress the state of wonder at the play of texts and interpretation.” (Culler, 1992, p. 122)Culler celebrates “wonder” as an essential quality for critical exploration, encouraging openness to imaginative and unexpected interpretations.
9. “The idea of ‘overinterpretation’ not only begs the question of which is to be preferred, but it also, I believe, fails to capture the problems Professor Eco himself wishes to address.” (Culler, 1992, p. 111)Culler challenges Eco’s dismissal of overinterpretation, arguing that it simplifies the complexity of interpretive challenges.
10. “A method that compels people to puzzle over not just those elements which might seem to resist the totalization of meaning… has a better chance of producing discoveries.” (Culler, 1992, p. 122)Culler advocates for interpretative methods that challenge readers to analyze seemingly trivial details, fostering discoveries about texts.
Suggested Readings: “In Defence Of Overinterpretation” by Jonathan Culler
  1. Gorman, David. “Jonathan Culler: A Checklist of Writings on Literary Criticism and Theory to 1994.” Style, vol. 29, no. 4, 1995, pp. 549–61. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/42946311. Accessed 17 Dec. 2024.
  2. Kaminski, Johannes. “Joys and Sorrows of Interpretation.” Lives and Deaths of Werther: Interpretation, Translation, and Adaptation in Europe and East Asia, The British Academy, 2023, pp. 21–69. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/jj.20829393.4. Accessed 17 Dec. 2024.
  3. Culler, Jonathan. “READERS AND READING.” On Deconstruction: Theory and Criticism after Structuralism, Cornell University Press, 1982, pp. 31–84. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.7591/j.ctt1ffjph5.6. Accessed 17 Dec. 2024.
  4. Culler, Jonathan. “In Defence of Overinterpretation, dalam Umberto Eco, Interpretation and Overinterpretation.” (1992).

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *