
Introduction: âOn Metaphor and Blendingâ by Gilles Fauconnier and George Lakoff
âOn Metaphor and Blendingâ by Gilles Fauconnier and George Lakoff first appeared as a collaborative response on the CogLing mailing list in 2008 and was later cited in The Cambridge Handbook of Metaphor and Thought (2008, ed. Raymond Gibbs). The piece offers a comprehensive reflection on the historical development, theoretical nuances, and mutual reinforcement of Conceptual Metaphor Theory (CMT) and Conceptual Blending Theory (CBT)âtwo foundational frameworks in cognitive linguistics. Fauconnier and Lakoff, countering the mistaken belief that their theories are in conflict, trace the evolution of both approaches: from the experiential mappings central to Metaphors We Live By (1980), through the neural grounding of metaphor in Lakoffâs later work (Philosophy in the Flesh, 1999), to the development of mental spaces and integration networks in Fauconnier and Turnerâs The Way We Think (2002). They argue that metaphor and blending operate at different levels of abstractionâblending synthesizes inputs from various mental spaces, while metaphor often structures those spaces through primary experiential correspondences. Crucially, the article insists that both approaches are empirically grounded and complementary: metaphor provides the foundational mappings, while blending enables complex integrations in thought and language, especially in literature, where poetic imagination often involves high-level generic metaphors embedded in richly blended mental spaces. In literary theory, this synthesis is vital for interpreting figurative language, poetic innovation, and narrative structure. Thus, this article stands as a pivotal contribution, reinforcing the compatibility of cognitive semantics with neural theory, and offering a unified vision for the study of meaning, imagination, and language in both scientific and literary domains.
Summary of âOn Metaphor and Blendingâ by Gilles Fauconnier and George Lakoff
đ No Theoretical Conflict: Complementary, Not Competing
- The article opens by dismissing the misconception that Conceptual Metaphor Theory (CMT) and Conceptual Blending Theory (CBT) are in opposition:
âThere is a mistaken perception that âmetaphor theoryâ and âconceptual blendingâ are competing views⊠The real situation is this: We have been good friends and colleagues for over forty years, and we remain soâ (Fauconnier & Lakoff, p. 394).
- Both approaches are portrayed as mutually reinforcing and often intertwined in theory and empirical scope.
đ§ Development of Conceptual Metaphor Theory (CMT)
- Initial formulation in Metaphors We Live By (1980): metaphors are cognitive mappings grounded in experiential domains.
âIt assumed that conceptual metaphors were cognitive mappings from frame to frame across domainsâ (p. 394).
- Mid-1980s: discovery of cross-linguistic metaphors and preservation of image-schema structures.
âThe crossâlinguistic ones all had common experiential bases⊠inferences that came with the imageâschema structureâ (p. 394).
- Generic-level metaphors: introduced in More Than Cool Reason (1989), mapping high-level abstractions onto specific, culturally framed instantiations.
âPoetic metaphors were typically made up of highâlevel generic content plus lowerâlevel contentâ (p. 394).
- Neural theory of metaphor (NTL): developed in the 1990s to model metaphor processing in the brain.
âIn the neural theory, the old âconceptual metaphorsâ are replaced by neural mappings, which are relatively simple neural circuitsâ (p. 395).
đ§© Emergence of Blending Theory and Mental Spaces
- Mental spaces introduced by Fauconnier (1977â1985) to handle logical phenomena in discourse.
âMental spaces and their connections were viewed as cognitive constructsâ (p. 395).
- Conceptual Blending (1990s): created by Fauconnier and Turner as an extension of mental spaces and metaphor mappings.
âA âconceptual blendâ used various mental spaces and mappings across them: A generic space, input spaces, and a blended spaceâ (p. 395).
- Blends allow creative cognitive operations not explained by metaphor alone, involving multiple mappings and emergent structure.
âBlending synthesizes mappings across inputs into a new, emergent spaceâ (p. 396).
đ§Ź Neural Integration: Mapping Metaphor and Blend to Brain Structures
- Lakoffâs neural linguistic model (late 1990sâ2000s) introduced neural constraints on conceptual mechanisms.
âAccording to Lakoff, neural binding circuitry is necessary to accomplish blending, but is insufficient for metaphorical mappingsâ (p. 396).
- The article emphasizes that neural blending and neural metaphor require distinct mechanisms.
âDifferent circuitry was neededâ (p. 396).
đ Blending Theory Incorporating Metaphor
- Fauconnier and Turner show that metaphor can be seen as a product of conceptual blending.
âMetaphors as surface products can result from complex integration networksâ (p. 397).
- Case study: âTIME as SPACEâ illustrates multiple layers of metaphor and blend working together.
âThis account⊠seems totally compatible with the binding mechanisms proposed within Neural Linguisticsâ (p. 397).
âïž Comparison of Theoretical Paradigms
- Lakoff and Fauconnier agree on the empirical validity of both theories but emphasize different analytic levels:
âThe different theoretical paradigms⊠do not necessarily yield exactly the same results, though there is considerable overlapâ (p. 397).
- Neural linguistics seeks to ground observed generalizations in neural circuitry:
âNeural linguistics⊠explain[s] at a deeper level, principles and generalizations discovered through linguistic analysisâ (p. 397).
đ§ Philosophy of Science and Methodology
- Clarification that both authors support data-driven cognitive linguistics, regardless of whether the method is experimental or observational:
âTraditional linguistic research⊠is one of the most important empirical methodologies in cognitive scienceâ (p. 398).
- They reject the notion that non-experimental work is âspeculativeâ or âunprovenâ:
âWe note a tendency to call anything thatâs not experimental, ânonâempiricalâ⊠We look forward to a return to that traditionâ (p. 398).
â€ïž Final Message: Unity in Diversity
- The essayâs final note underscores the complementarity of metaphor and blending theories:
âThere would be no conceptual blending framework without conceptual metaphor theory, and there would be no neural linguistics without the elaborate linguistic analysisâ (p. 398).
- Their collaboration reflects a model for interdisciplinary integration:
âDifferent enterprises⊠can mutually reinforce each other, lead to deeper convergent perspectives, and achieve wide-ranging scientific goalsâ (p. 397).
Theoretical Terms/Concepts in âOn Metaphor and Blendingâ by Gilles Fauconnier and George Lakoff
đ§ Theoretical Term | đ Explanation | đ Reference / Quotation |
đ Conceptual Metaphor (CMT) | A cognitive mapping from a source domain to a target domain, often grounded in embodied experience. Fundamental to how we understand abstract ideas through concrete ones. | âConceptual metaphors were cognitive mappings from frame to frame across domainsâ (p. 394). |
đ§© Conceptual Blending (CBT) | Combines elements from multiple mental spaces to create a new, emergent conceptual space with novel inferences and structure. | âA conceptual blend used various mental spaces and mappings across themâ (p. 395). |
đ Mental Spaces | Temporary, dynamic cognitive constructs used to track meaning in discourse and enable flexible inferencing, central to blending theory. | âMental spaces and their connections were viewed as cognitive constructsâ (p. 395). |
đ Generic Space | An abstract structure common to multiple input spaces; it supports integration in blending by allowing partial projection of structure. | âA generic space, input spaces, and a blended spaceâŠâ (p. 395). |
đ§ź Image Schemas | Recurrent patterns from sensorimotor experience (e.g., CONTAINER, PATH) that underlie conceptual metaphors and structure cognition. | âMetaphorical mappings appeared to âpreserve image schema structureââŠâ (p. 394). |
đ§Ź Neural Binding | The mechanism in which different neural components are dynamically linked to enable complex concepts, including blends and metaphors, to be represented. | âNeural binding circuitry is necessary to accomplish blendingâŠâ (p. 396). |
đ§ Neural Theory of Metaphor | A model proposing that metaphors are instantiated in the brain as neural circuits, formed through early embodied experiences. | âThe old âconceptual metaphorsâ are replaced by neural mappings, which are relatively simple neural circuitsâ (p. 395). |
âïž Primary Metaphors | Basic metaphorical mappings derived from universal bodily experiences (e.g., AFFECTION IS WARMTH, MORE IS UP). These serve as building blocks for complex metaphors. | âCentering on âprimary metaphorsâ â Philosophy in the FleshâŠâ (p. 395). |
đ Surface Metaphors | The linguistic expressions (e.g., phrases, idioms) that reflect underlying conceptual metaphors or blended structures. | âMetaphors as surface products can result from complex integration networksâŠâ (p. 397). |
đŻ Optimality Principles | Cognitive constraints guiding how blends are constructed (e.g., achieving integration, avoiding clash, maximizing relevance). | âFormulation of governing principles and optimality constraints on blending processesâ (p. 396). |
đ§ Integration Networks | Systems of interconnected mental spaces, including inputs, generic, and blended spaces, used in constructing conceptual blends. | âCompression in integration networks⊠empirically based theoretical advanceâ (p. 396). |
đ§Ș Empirical Semantics | A methodology emphasizing extensive analysis of linguistic data to derive cognitive generalizations, distinct from solely experimental approaches. | âThe analysis of massive amounts of linguistic data â especially in the area of semanticsâ (p. 398). |
Contribution of âOn Metaphor and Blendingâ by Gilles Fauconnier and George Lakoff to Literary Theory/Theories
đ Poetic Metaphor Theory (Lakoff & Turnerâs Model)
- Contribution: The article reinforces the idea that poetic metaphors are not merely decorative language but are cognitively structured through high-level generic mappings and frame-specific instantiations.
- Reference: âPoetic metaphors were typically made up of highâlevel generic content plus lowerâlevel contentâ (p. 394).
- Implication: In literary theory, this supports the view that poetic language reveals structured conceptual patterns, making CMT a tool for analyzing literary expression and figurative depth.
đ§ Cognitive Poetics / Cognitive Literary Theory
- Contribution: Blending theory expands literary analysis beyond metaphor, allowing for the examination of how multiple input spaces are merged to create novel imaginative meaningsâessential in poetry, allegory, and myth.
- Reference: âA conceptual blend used various mental spaces and mappings across them: A generic space, input spaces, and a blended spaceâ (p. 395).
- Implication: Literary texts often involve multiple conceptual mappings (metaphorical, metonymic, fictional), and blending theory accounts for their integration and emergent properties in narrative and lyrical structure.
đź Symbolism and Allegory Analysis
- Contribution: The theory of integration networks and optimality constraints helps explain how literary allegories operate by compressing elaborate mappings into symbolic forms.
- Reference: âCompression in integration networks⊠allowed the formulation of governing principles and optimality constraintsâ (p. 396).
- Implication: Complex symbols in literature (e.g., âthe ship of stateâ or âthe veil in The Scarlet Letterâ) are cognitive blends that can be unpacked using blending theory, revealing layered meanings.
đ Intertextuality and Frame-Shifting
- Contribution: The article supports the idea of mental space construction across texts, which aligns with theories of intertextuality and frame-shifting in poststructuralist and cognitive frameworks.
- Reference: âFrameshifting and Conceptual Blending in Meaning Constructionâ (Coulson, 2001, cited p. 399).
- Implication: Readers construct intertextual meaning by shifting between cognitive frames and input spaces; blending theory explains how this happens at a mental-structural level.
đĄ Figurative Language and Embodied Meaning
- Contribution: Conceptual metaphor and blending are grounded in embodied cognition, showing that even abstract literary language is rooted in physical experience.
- Reference: âConceptual metaphors⊠were cognitive mappings⊠grounded in experienceâ (p. 394); âprimary metaphors⊠Philosophy in the Fleshâ (p. 395).
- Implication: This supports embodied theories of meaning in literature, where metaphors are not stylistic flourishes but reflections of sensorimotor patterns.
đ§° Narratology and Viewpoint Theory
- Contribution: Mental space theory contributes to understanding narrative voice, temporal shifts, and viewpoint in literature.
- Reference: âMental space constructions accounted for tense and viewpoint phenomena in languageâ (p. 395, citing Cutrer, 1994).
- Implication: Tools from mental space theory help narratologists model how readers shift between character and narrator perspectives in complex narratives.
đ Distributed and Material Cognition in Literary Contexts
- Contribution: The role of material anchors in blends (Hutchins, 2005) shows how literary objects (e.g., maps, clocks, diagrams) can participate in meaning-making through cognitive blending.
- Reference: âMaterial anchors⊠showing the role of blending in material cultureâ (p. 396).
- Implication: Material features in literary texts (e.g., visual poetry, graphic novels) are part of cognitive operationsânot just aesthetic elements.
đ§Ș Empirical Basis for Figurative Analysis
- Contribution: The article defends the empirical rigor of linguistic analysis in literary semantics, countering views that only experimental methods count as valid science.
- Reference: âThe analysis of massive amounts of linguistic data â especially in the area of semanticsâ (p. 398).
- Implication: Validates cognitive approaches in literary theory as data-rich and empirically structured, not speculative.
đ§ Literary Creativity as Cognitive Construction
- Contribution: Literary innovation, particularly metaphorical and narrative creativity, is explained not as mysticism but as systematic conceptual integration.
- Reference: âMetaphors and blends are among the most interesting phenomena in the cognitive sciences, and should be studied in enormous detailâ (p. 398).
- Implication: Literary creativity is modeled as cognitive engineering using available conceptual resourcesâbridging creativity and structured cognition.
Examples of Critiques Through âOn Metaphor and Blendingâ by Gilles Fauconnier and George Lakoff
đŒïž Literary Work | đ§ Cognitive Theory Applied | đ Critical Insight Using CMT & CBT |
đŠ The Metamorphosis by Franz Kafka | đ Conceptual Metaphor & đ§© Conceptual Blending | The surreal transformation of Gregor into an insect results from a blend of input spaces â human identity + vermin â producing a metaphor for existential alienation. Underlying metaphors include SELF IS OTHER and LIFE IS A BURDEN (p. 395). |
đ âOde to a Nightingaleâ by John Keats | đ§ Generic Metaphor, đ§© Integration Networks, đ Mental Spaces | The speakerâs movement into the nightingaleâs world is a blended space combining poetic consciousness and mythical immortality. Utilizes the TIME-AS-SPACE metaphor (p. 397), showing a cognitive escape from mortality into aesthetic timelessness. |
đ§ Moby-Dick by Herman Melville | đ Mental Spaces, âïž Primary Metaphors, đŻ Optimality Principles | Ahabâs pursuit constructs a blend between man, monomania, and cosmic force. The white whale becomes a conceptual blend of nature, divinity, and personal vengeance, structured by primary metaphors like KNOWING IS SEEING, OBSESSION IS WAR (p. 396). |
đč âThe Waste Landâ by T.S. Eliot | đ Generic Space, đ§© Blending, đ Surface Metaphors | Eliotâs fragmented voices construct overlapping mental spaces from mythology, modern decay, and postwar trauma. Blends produce a composite cultural consciousness, where APRIL IS CRUELTY becomes a surface metaphor born of emergent meaning through compression (p. 396â397). |
Criticism Against âOn Metaphor and Blendingâ by Gilles Fauconnier and George Lakoff
âïž Overgeneralization of Cognitive Mechanisms
- Critics argue that conceptual metaphor and blending frameworks sometimes overextend their explanatory scope, attempting to account for all forms of meaning construction.
The flexibility of blending theory risks making it âtoo powerful,â capable of explaining everything but predicting nothing.
đ§Ș Lack of Empirical Falsifiability
- Despite being labeled âempirical,â both theories face criticism for insufficient experimental testability.
âWe note a tendency to call anything thatâs not experimental, ânonâempiricalââ (p. 398), yet critics argue the theories still rely heavily on introspective analysis rather than rigorous data.
đ Ambiguity in Mapping Levels
- Thereâs inconsistent terminology across metaphor and blending theory, especially between surface metaphors and deep conceptual mappings.
The article itself admits: âThe word âmetaphorâ is ambiguous between such conceptual mappings⊠and surface products also called âmetaphorsââ (p. 395).
đ Blending Theoryâs Circularity
- Some scholars claim that blending theory is descriptively circular â explaining literary creativity by restating the inputs and outputs without revealing cognitive necessity.
Thereâs a lack of predictive structure to determine when and how blends will emerge.
đ§Ź Disconnection Between Neural and Conceptual Models
- Although neural linguistics is a major part of Lakoffâs approach, critics point to a gap between theoretical mappings and actual neural evidence.
âThe blending theoryâs generalization across mappings⊠did not hold at the neural levelâ (p. 396), showing unresolved tension between theory and neuroscience.
đ§© Insufficient Differentiation from Classical Semantics
- Critics argue that while CMT and CBT reject classical semantics, they donât always offer clear formal alternatives for semantics in syntax, logic, or truth-conditional terms.
âł Underestimation of Historical and Cultural Specificity
- Conceptual metaphor theory has been challenged for its universalizing tendencies, often neglecting historical and cultural variation in metaphor use.
Literary critics argue that CMT sometimes flattens textual richness into cognitive templates.
đ Limited Literary Sensitivity
- Some literary theorists claim that the cognitive models do not account for style, irony, genre, and aesthetic form, limiting their applicability to close literary analysis.
đ Reductive View of Figurative Language
- Figurative expressions that are layered, ironic, or ambiguous are sometimes too reductively mapped onto embodied metaphors or image schemas.
Critics suggest this misses intentional poetic ambiguity and interpretive openness.
Representative Quotations from âOn Metaphor and Blendingâ by Gilles Fauconnier and George Lakoff with Explanation
đŹ Quotation | đ Explanation / Relevance | |
đ | âConceptual metaphors were cognitive mappings from frame to frame across domains.â (p. 394) | Establishes the foundational claim of Conceptual Metaphor Theory (CMT) â metaphor is a cross-domain mapping in cognition. |
đ§© | âA conceptual blend used various mental spaces and mappings across them: A generic space, input spaces, and a blended space.â (p. 395) | Defines how blending operates using structured mental spaces â core to Conceptual Blending Theory (CBT). |
đ€ | âWe see the research programs developed for metaphor and blending as mutually reinforcing and often deeply intertwined, rather than at odds with each other.â (p. 394) | The authors assert theoretical harmony between CMT and CBT, emphasizing their collaboration and convergence. |
âïž | âPoetic metaphors were typically made up of highâlevel generic content plus lowerâlevel content, typically from frames.â (p. 394) | Clarifies the layered construction of poetic metaphors using both abstract and contextual cognitive structures. |
đ§Ź | âNeural binding circuitry is necessary to accomplish blending, but is insufficient for metaphorical mappings.â (p. 396) | Differentiates the neural underpinnings of blending and metaphor, pointing to distinct cognitive architectures. |
đ | âMental spaces and their connections were viewed as cognitive constructs.â (p. 395) | Describes mental spaces as core building blocks of meaning-making in CBT, created dynamically in cognition. |
đŻ | âThis was an empirically based theoretical advance, that allowed the formulation of governing principles and optimality constraints on blending processes.â (p. 396) | Refers to the formalization of CBT through empirical patterns â showing how blends are shaped by cognitive constraints. |
đ | âThe word âmetaphorâ itself is ambiguous between such conceptual mappings between spaces, and surface products also called âmetaphorsâ, which can result from multiple mappings and blending.â (p. 395) | Identifies a key semantic ambiguity in linguistic and literary analysis of metaphor. |
đ§Ș | âBut we note a tendency to call anything thatâs not experimental, ânonâempiricalâ and so by implication âspeculativeâ, âunprovenâ, etc.â (p. 398) | Challenges narrow definitions of scientific method and defends empirical theoretical linguistics. |
đ | âDifferent enterprises developed with seemingly different purposes and different theoretical constructs can mutually reinforce each other, lead to deeper convergent perspectives, and achieve wide-ranging scientific goals.â (p. 398) | Advocates for interdisciplinary collaboration and theoretical integration â a cornerstone of this articleâs message. |
Suggested Readings: âOn Metaphor and Blendingâ by Gilles Fauconnier and George Lakoff
- Lakoff, George, and Mark Johnson. âConceptual Metaphor in Everyday Language.â The Journal of Philosophy, vol. 77, no. 8, 1980, pp. 453â86. JSTOR, https://doi.org/10.2307/2025464. Accessed 11 June 2025.
- Lakoff, George. âMETAPHOR AND WAR: THE METAPHOR SYSTEM USED TO JUSTIFY WAR IN THE GULF.â Peace Research, vol. 23, no. 2/3, 1991, pp. 25â32. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/23609916. Accessed 11 June 2025.
- Stelzner, Hermann G. âON TEACHING A COLLEGE COURSE ON METAPHOR.â ETC: A Review of General Semantics, vol. 48, no. 2, 1991, pp. 200â03. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/42577283. Accessed 11 June 2025.