“Metaphor in Linguistic Thought and Theory” by Ronald W. Langacker: Summary and Critique

“Metaphor in Linguistic Thought and Theory” by Ronald W. Langacker first appeared in Cognitive Semantics, Volume 2 (2016), published by Koninklijke Brill NV. In this seminal article, Langacker argues that metaphor is not merely a stylistic or rhetorical device but a foundational and inescapable element of linguistic thought, theory formation, and conceptual modeling.

"Metaphor in Linguistic Thought and Theory" by Ronald W. Langacker: Summary and Critique
Introduction: “Metaphor in Linguistic Thought and Theory” by Ronald W. Langacker

“Metaphor in Linguistic Thought and Theory” by Ronald W. Langacker first appeared in Cognitive Semantics, Volume 2 (2016), published by Koninklijke Brill NV. In this seminal article, Langacker argues that metaphor is not merely a stylistic or rhetorical device but a foundational and inescapable element of linguistic thought, theory formation, and conceptual modeling. He critiques the pervasive, yet often unexamined, reliance on metaphor in linguistic discourse—from the container metaphor of lexicon to the computational metaphors of grammar and cognition. Drawing on cognitive linguistics, Langacker proposes that both formalist and functionalist frameworks are shaped by distinct metaphorical worldviews: the former favoring object-like, discrete metaphors, and the latter embracing more population-based, emergent structures. He dissects influential models such as the schema and exemplar approaches, ultimately concluding that their apparent opposition is largely metaphorical and not theoretically substantive. The article is important in literary theory and broader humanistic scholarship because it emphasizes the epistemic consequences of metaphorical thinking in the construction of scientific paradigms and critiques the illusion of objectivity that metaphor often conceals. It calls for increased vigilance in identifying and evaluating metaphors as conceptual tools that shape, limit, and potentially mislead theoretical understanding. Langacker’s nuanced, sometimes satirical prose reinforces his central message: that metaphor is both the engine and the hazard of theoretical insight.

Theoretical Terms/Concepts in “Metaphor in Linguistic Thought and Theory” by Ronald W. Langacker

🌍 Metaphor Is Inescapable and Central to Linguistic Thought

  • Metaphor is not merely ornamental; it permeates all levels of linguistic theory—from terminology to worldviews.

“Metaphor is not just prevalent in linguistics but utterly pervasive, especially at the theoretical level” (© Langacker, 2016, p. 5).

  • Langacker satirizes the “moralistic” view of metaphor as sinful, suggesting its inevitability.

“Let him who is without metaphor cast the first stone” (© p. 4).


🧠 Cognitive Models Depend on Metaphoric Frameworks

  • Linguistic thinking draws from source domains like motion, space, genetics, and visual perception.

“Common metaphorical source domains are well represented: spatial motion, plants, genetic relationships…” (© p. 6).

  • Terms like “raising,” “tree,” “node,” “focus,” “field” are metaphorical yet deeply embedded in linguistic discourse.

“[W]e find the linguistic landscape to be littered with countless metaphoric terms…” (© p. 5).


🧱 Metaphorical Worldviews Shape Theoretical Divides

  • The formalist vs. functionalist divide is understood via isoglosses or dialect chains (discrete vs. continuous metaphors).

“A thick bundle of metaphoric isoglosses separates the two communities” (© p. 7).

  • Formalist metaphor: language is a machine or assembly line assembling discrete objects.

“Language was represented as a box labeled G… constructing step by step…” (© p. 8).

  • Functionalist metaphor: language as a population or network of interacting, emergent elements.

“They favor population metaphors… like people in a society” (© p. 9).


🔁 Metaphor as Double-Edged Sword: Tool and Threat

  • Metaphor can clarify but also confuse: it can lead to misleading questions, conceptual errors, and unproductive debates.

“Metaphor is seductive… it will lead us into temptation” (© p. 10).

  • Examples of misguided metaphors include viewing lexemes as containers and the lexicon as a physical store.

“The lexicon is a container for storing lexical items… which in turn are containers…” (© p. 11).


📦 Network vs. ☁️ Field Model: Not Truly Opposed

  • Network model (Lakoff, Langacker): meaning as interconnected nodes; Field model (Allwood, Zlatev): continuous range of uses.

“A continuous range of ‘meaning potential’… the union of individually or collectively remembered uses” (© p. 14).

  • Langacker shows these metaphors can coexist, e.g., using the mountain range metaphor.

“An element’s range of meanings [is like] a mountain range… peaks in a continuous expanse” (© p. 15).


🧰 Tools, Not Truths: The Proper Use of Metaphor

  • Metaphors should be treated as heuristics, not literal truths.

“We must try to be aware of the metaphors we are using, their limitations…” (© p. 16).

  • Multiple metaphors provide checks and balances, enhancing insight.

“Alternative metaphors make it easier to distinguish the target from its metaphorical construal” (© p. 27).


🧬 Schema vs. Exemplar Models: Apparent vs. Real Distinctions

  • Both models rely on usage-based knowledge, memory traces, and reinforcement of patterns.

“A schema is nothing more than a coarse-grained representation of occurring instances” (© p. 19).

  • The exemplar model (e.g., Pierrehumbert) stores individual token memories as “clouds”, but still shows schematicity.

“[A]n exemplar model… each category is represented in memory by a large cloud of remembered tokens” (© p. 17).

  • The differences are metaphorical, not substantive.

“There is no fundamental difference” between schemas and exemplar clusters (© p. 24).


⛰️ State-Space and Dynamic Landscape Metaphors

  • Langacker suggests visualizing meaning categories as landscapes with valleys (attractors) rather than boxes.

“We take the image of a mountain range and turn it upside down… a landscape with depressions” (© p. 26).

  • Both network and exemplar models fit within this dynamic attractor metaphor.

“The height of a peak—or the depth of a depression—corresponds to entrenchment…” (© p. 26).


🧭 Concluding Thoughts: Taming the Metaphoric Mind

  • Metaphor is inevitable, yet manageable with awareness, flexibility, and alternative framing.

“If we are never free of metaphor… we can at least operate at a lower level of confusion” (© p. 27).

  • Rather than being controlled by metaphor, scholars can use it judiciously as a guide.

“We are not just helpless prisoners of metaphor… it is a tool that we can use…” (© p. 27).

Contribution of “Metaphor in Linguistic Thought and Theory” by Ronald W. Langacker to Literary Theory/Theories

📚 1. Structuralism → Metaphor as Systemic Organizing Principle

  • Langacker challenges the structuralist notion of fixed systems with discrete parts (Saussurean linguistics), showing that metaphor pervades even “systematic” linguistic theory.

“The grammar of a language was thought of as a machine… where well-formed sentences were constructed step by step and given as ‘output’” (© p. 8).

  • This critique aligns with post-structuralist skepticism about neat structural binaries (e.g. langue/parole, signifier/signified).
    Contribution: Undermines structuralist rigidity by emphasizing metaphor’s creative and destabilizing role within linguistic systems.

🔁 2. Post-Structuralism / Deconstruction → Metaphor as Conceptual Instability

  • Langacker argues that metaphors, while helpful heuristics, are inherently unstable, misleading, and conflicting.

“We must try to be aware of the metaphors we are using, their limitations…” (© p. 16).

  • Similar to Derrida’s idea of différance, metaphors defer fixed meaning and introduce slippages.
    Contribution: Shows how linguistic theories themselves collapse under the weight of their own metaphors, revealing aporetic tensions within meaning-making structures.

🧠 3. Cognitive Literary Theory → Embodied Metaphor in Conceptual Understanding

  • Builds on Lakoff and Johnson’s idea of conceptual metaphor, reinforcing that thought is metaphorical at its core.

“It is part of the human condition that metaphor is inevitable…” (© p. 15).

  • Literary theory adopting a cognitive approach (e.g. Turner, Zunshine) gains support: literature relies on the same neural metaphor systems used in linguistic theory.
    Contribution: Confirms that literary metaphors are not just stylistic but grounded in cognitive mechanisms shared with scientific reasoning.

⚖️ 4. Reader-Response Theory → Interpretive Flexibility of Metaphor

  • Langacker’s discussion of metaphor generating different construals (e.g. networks vs. fields) parallels reader-response theory: meaning is contextual, flexible, and reader-shaped.

“It may be that each [metaphor] is efficacious within certain limits but gives a distorted view of the target when it stands alone…” (© p. 14).

  • Just as readers construct meaning through interaction with text, scholars construe meaning through metaphor.
    Contribution: Supports the active role of interpreters in constructing meaning via metaphor, echoing Stanley Fish and Louise Rosenblatt.

🎨 5. Rhetorical and Tropological Theories → Metaphor Beyond Ornamentation

  • Langacker rejects the notion of metaphor as merely decorative: it is a constitutive force in theoretical discourse.

“Metaphor is not just unavoidable but essential… a source of insight and creativity” (© p. 3).

  • Supports theorists like Paul de Man and Kenneth Burke, who argued that rhetoric (especially metaphor) shapes thought.
    Contribution: Aligns linguistic and literary theories in treating metaphor as foundational rather than supplemental.

🌀 6. Phenomenology & Hermeneutics → Metaphor as Lived, Embodied Experience

  • His emphasis on embodied cognition and usage-based linguistics echoes Merleau-Ponty’s and Gadamer’s phenomenological focus.

“The basic noun classes accommodate basic aspects of embodied experience” (© p. 9).

  • Interpretation is shaped not by abstract structures but by bodily, lived metaphorical understanding.
    Contribution: Strengthens literary hermeneutics by showing metaphor as experience-structured, not just symbolically derived.

🏗️ 7. Critical Discourse Theory → Ideological Power of Metaphor

  • Langacker reveals how theoretical language constructs social and ideological boundaries, e.g., formalist vs. functionalist metaphors create camps or dialect zones.

“A thick bundle of metaphoric isoglosses separates the two communities…” (© p. 7).

  • Echoes Foucault, Bourdieu, and Fairclough: discourse (and its metaphors) organizes knowledge and power.
    Contribution: Offers insight into how disciplinary ideologies are constructed, legitimated, and naturalized via metaphor.

🌐 8. Interdisciplinary Theory / Philosophy of Language → Language as Epistemological Tool

  • Demonstrates that metaphor is not a contamination of scientific objectivity, but a core epistemological tool.

“We normally have some independent knowledge… which we can use to check a metaphor’s appropriateness…” (© p. 27).

  • Bridges linguistics, cognitive science, and literary studies, much like Nelson Goodman or Rorty.
    Contribution: Advances cross-disciplinary understanding of metaphor as a mode of inquiry across sciences and humanities.

🧩 9. New Materialism / Complexity Theory → Emergence and Network Models

  • Describes language categories as emergent phenomena in networks, not fixed structures.

“Networks have numerous applications in cognitive and functional linguistics… [they] are accessed in different combinations” (© p. 10).

  • Aligns with new materialist and non-linear systems theory perspectives (e.g. Jane Bennett, Deleuze).
    Contribution: Reframes literary meaning as emergent, distributed, and dynamic, not centered or hierarchical.

Examples of Critiques Through “Metaphor in Linguistic Thought and Theory” by Ronald W. Langacker
📘 Literary Work🧠 Langackerian Metaphor Framework🔍 Critique via Langacker’s Theory
🧊 Frankenstein by Mary ShelleyObject Metaphor → Language and mind as modular “containers” (© pp. 8–9)Victor’s scientific vision mirrors the formalist metaphor of language as a compartmentalized machine. The creature resists “categorical containment,” exposing the dangers of excessive modular metaphoric thinking. Langacker’s critique of object metaphors shows how emotional and ethical complexity is lost when thought is over-systematized.
🌿 The Waste Land by T.S. EliotNetwork and Population Metaphors → Lexical meaning as a web of usage-based nodes (© pp. 10–11)Eliot’s fragmented narrative resists singular interpretation, akin to Langacker’s network model, where meaning emerges from interconnected yet shifting semantic nodes. The text thrives on polysemous resonance rather than fixed meaning, illustrating the power of metaphors that emphasize continuity and emergence.
🕸️ Beloved by Toni MorrisonField/Cloud Metaphor → Semantic potential as diffuse and context-sensitive (© pp. 12–14, 22–24)Morrison’s narrative of trauma reflects semantic cloudiness—not a network of discrete meanings, but an amorphous field of affect and memory. Langacker’s field metaphor helps explain how meanings cluster and shift, and how characters move through semantic valleys and peaks of remembrance.
🔨 1984 by George OrwellConduit Metaphor + Language-of-Thought Critique (© pp. 12–13)Orwell’s Newspeak enacts the conduit metaphor, where words “contain” and transmit thought. Langacker warns this is misleading reification, as language does not store meaning in fixed units. Orwell’s dystopia reflects the danger of literalizing metaphor, a caution Langacker insists upon: metaphors must be used vigilantly or risk distorting cognition and ideology.
Criticism Against “Metaphor in Linguistic Thought and Theory” by Ronald W. Langacker

🎯 Overreliance on Metaphor as Cognitive Necessity

  • Langacker claims metaphor is inevitable and essential to theory-building, but this may undervalue formal, literal, and empirical models that aim for conceptual precision.
  • Critics may argue that such a stance blurs the boundary between analytical reasoning and rhetorical strategy, leading to potential epistemological relativism.

🔄 Self-Contradictory Treatment of Reification

  • Langacker criticizes reification (e.g., treating schemas or meanings as static entities) yet himself reifies schemas, networks, clouds, and fields through sustained metaphorical imagery.
  • This introduces an inconsistency: metaphor is described as both indispensable and misleading, which weakens the argument’s internal coherence.

🧩 Ambiguity in Model Distinctions (Schema vs. Exemplar)

  • While Langacker attempts to reconcile schema and exemplar models, some may find his resolution too conciliatory and conceptually blurred.
  • By proposing that “clouds” and “schemas” are ultimately the same, he dilutes the analytical utility of each model, flattening critical distinctions.

🌀 Philosophical Circularity in Metaphor Critique

  • Langacker critiques metaphors using other metaphors (e.g., object vs. population, cloud vs. mountain range), creating a kind of meta-metaphorical loop.
  • This may result in circular reasoning, where metaphor is both the problem and solution, offering no non-metaphorical ground for judgment.

📏 Lack of Operational Criteria for “Appropriateness”

  • The discussion frequently refers to metaphors being “more or less appropriate,” yet no clear metric or framework is provided to evaluate metaphorical adequacy.
  • This weakens the methodological rigor of the analysis and may limit its applicability across linguistic subfields or empirical studies.

🛠️ Underemphasis on Empirical Validation

  • The article offers philosophical reflection and theoretical comparison, but it lacks empirical data or experimental findings that could ground metaphor use in observable cognitive behavior.
  • This opens it to criticism from scholars favoring corpus-based, psycholinguistic, or experimental paradigms.

🔍 Inadequate Attention to Cross-Linguistic Diversity

  • While addressing metaphor in linguistic theory, Langacker focuses mostly on Anglophone linguistic traditions, ignoring cross-cultural metaphorical frameworks (e.g., in non-Indo-European languages).
  • This undermines claims about universality or inevitability of metaphor in linguistic cognition.

📚 Limited Engagement with Literary and Poetic Metaphor

  • Despite the rich analysis of theoretical metaphors, Langacker largely avoids addressing metaphor as it functions in literary, poetic, or socio-political discourse, which could offer richer contrast.
  • This may leave the metaphorical spectrum underexplored, especially regarding non-scientific genres.
Representative Quotations from “Metaphor in Linguistic Thought and Theory” by Ronald W. Langacker with Explanation
📌 Quotation 💡 Explanation
“🌀 Metaphor is not just unavoidable but essential to the enterprise, a source of insight and creativity.” (p. 3)Langacker asserts that metaphor is a foundational mechanism in linguistic theorizing—not merely rhetorical, but constitutive of conceptual understanding.
“⚠️ All metaphors are inappropriate in some respect… They can lead to spurious questions, conceptual confusion, misconception of the target, and pointless arguments.” (p. 3)Despite their usefulness, metaphors are inherently limited and can derail rigorous analysis if taken too literally.
“🏗️ It would not be entirely inappropriate to regard languages in their diachronic aspect as gigantic expression-compacting machines…” (p. 4)This industrial metaphor illustrates how language evolution compresses, erodes, and simplifies expressions—warning of reductive conceptual habits.
“🧱 There was first the conception of language as a distinct mental ‘organ’… represented as a box labeled G…” (p. 8)Langacker critiques the rigid ‘object metaphors’ of formalism that reify grammar into mechanistic, boxed systems.
“🌐 Functionalists steer a middle course… a mass-like population of discrete elements…” (p. 9)Introduces a “population” metaphor contrasting formalist rigidity, highlighting how functionalist approaches embrace flexible linguistic categorization.
“🌄 We might distort things less by comparing an element’s range of meanings to a mountain range…” (p. 15)This topographical metaphor models lexical meaning as a terrain of peaks (salient senses) and valleys (semantic ambiguity), favoring gradation over strict boundaries.
“🧠 Schemas are immanent in their instantiations… overlapping patterns of activity.” (p. 21)Clarifies that schemas are not external constructs but internalized, dynamic, and emergent from language use itself.
“🌩️ Metaphor is seductive… it will lead us into temptation, down the path of iniquity, in the form of unrestrained metaphoric excess.” (p. 11)A vivid, biblical warning: metaphor can become misleading theology if uncritically indulged, despite being cognitively unavoidable.
“🧰 Having alternative metaphors… makes them visible… keeps us from confusing the metaphorical construal from the target itself.” (p. 27)Promotes critical metaphor awareness: using multiple metaphors reveals the constructed nature of theory and prevents dogmatism.
“🔁 If particles and waves happily co-exist as metaphors for light, why not networks and fields for lexical meaning?” (p. 14)Advocates metaphorical pluralism—multiple metaphors can coexist and enrich theory, just as physics accepts wave-particle duality.
Suggested Readings: “Metaphor in Linguistic Thought and Theory” by Ronald W. Langacker
  1. Ben-Amos, Dan. “Metaphor.” Journal of Linguistic Anthropology, vol. 9, no. 1/2, 1999, pp. 152–54. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/43102452. Accessed 12 May 2025.
  2. Levin, Samuel R. “Aristotle’s Theory of Metaphor.” Philosophy & Rhetoric, vol. 15, no. 1, 1982, pp. 24–46. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/40237305. Accessed 12 May 2025.
  3. Underhill, James W. “Other Developments in Metaphor Theory.” Creating Worldviews: Metaphor, Ideology and Language, Edinburgh University Press, 2011, pp. 30–43. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.3366/j.ctt1r23vv.7. Accessed 12 May 2025.
  4. Miller, Donald F. “METAPHOR, THINKING, AND THOUGHT.” ETC: A Review of General Semantics, vol. 39, no. 2, 1982, pp. 134–50. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/42575924. Accessed 12 May 2025.

“Metaphor Revisited” by Dennis Sobolev: Summary and Critique

“Metaphor Revisited” by Dennis Sobolev first appeared in New Literary History, Volume 39, Number 4 (Autumn 2008), published by Johns Hopkins University Press.

"Metaphor Revisited" by Dennis Sobolev: Summary and Critique
Introduction: “Metaphor Revisited” by Dennis Sobolev

“Metaphor Revisited” by Dennis Sobolev first appeared in New Literary History, Volume 39, Number 4 (Autumn 2008), published by Johns Hopkins University Press. This article provides a far-reaching reassessment of metaphor in literature, challenging prevailing theoretical models by conceptualizing metaphor not as a unitary structure but as a multidimensional field organized along several independent analytical axes. Sobolev argues that previous scholarly approaches—ranging from structuralist, analytic, and cognitive traditions—have often failed to accommodate the heterogeneity and complex functioning of metaphor in literary discourse. Crucially, he distinguishes between the structure of identification (how metaphors are recognized) and the structure of functioning (how metaphors operate and produce meaning), asserting that the former cannot fully account for the cognitive or aesthetic impact of metaphors. Sobolev also introduces a tripartite model of metaphor consisting of the frame, the primary term, and the secondary term, enhancing existing dichotomies such as I. A. Richards’s “tenor and vehicle” or Max Black’s “focus and frame.” The essay maps metaphor’s diverse modalities across axes like interaction vs. transference, intelligible vs. perceptual similarity, creation vs. elucidation, and identification vs. juxtaposition, demonstrating that most metaphors combine functions in varying proportions rather than belonging to exclusive categories. By integrating insights from classical rhetoric, contemporary philosophy of language, and cognitive linguistics, Sobolev repositions metaphor as a dynamic epistemological tool central to cultural and literary synthesis. His work is pivotal for literary theory as it reveals the limitations of reductionist approaches and offers a richer, more nuanced conceptual framework for metaphorical discourse.

Summary of “Metaphor Revisited” by Dennis Sobolev

🧠 Theoretical Significance of Metaphor

  • Metaphor remains central across disciplines, especially in literary theory despite shifts from structuralist to postmodern paradigms.
  • Structuralist models (like those of the Prague School and French structuralism) emphasized metaphor as a fundamental linguistic operation.

“Metaphor may serve as a good case study and thus as a model of the analysis of the operations of synthesis in general.” (p. 904)


🪞 Structure of Metaphor: Not Unified but Multidimensional

  • Metaphor is not a singular structure but a field of heterogeneous possibilities, organized along several independent axes.

“Metaphor… is not a single unified structure, but rather a field of heterogeneous possibilities… limited by border parameters.” (p. 904)

  • Sobolev challenges simplified models like tenor and vehicle (Richards) and focus/frame (Black), proposing a tripartite structure:
    Frame – Primary Term – Secondary Term.

🔍 Identification vs Function

  • Two central questions:
    1. Structure of Identification – How we recognize a metaphor.
    2. Structure of Functioning – How metaphors operate and affect cognition and emotion.

“It is insufficient to know how metaphors are identified in order to explain the essence of their functioning.” (p. 906)


⚙️ Identification Conditions: Necessary & Sufficient

  • Sobolev presents 9 types of necessary conditions (logical contradiction, conceptual incongruity, etc.)
  • Sufficient condition: foregrounded similarity between terms.

“In a metaphor… a similarity between the terms… plays a central role in the production of meaning.” (p. 910)


📐 Axes of Metaphorical Analysis (12 Axes Model)

Sobolev introduces 12 axes, each describing different facets of metaphor:

🌈 1. Type of Interaction

From transference (simple projection of attributes) to foregrounding (interactive discovery of meaning).

“All empirical metaphors are situated along the axis… marked as ‘transference’ and ‘foregrounding’.” (p. 913)

🔁 2. Truth vs Success

Some metaphors can be true/false, others successful/unsuccessful in interpretation.

“’The mind has mountains’ is neither true nor false… but the interaction… is definitely successful.” (p. 914)

🔬 3. Type of Similarity

From given (pre-existing) to produced (created by the metaphor).

🧭 4. Purpose of Synthesis

From elucidation (illustrating known concepts) to creation (introducing new concepts, i.e., catachresis).

🧩 5. Form of Similarity

From objective grounding to cultural convention.

🔗 6. Modality of Similarity

From substantial (about objects) to relational (about relationships).

👁️ 7. Cognitive Mode

From intelligible to perceptible (whether metaphor requires visualization or not).

“Metaphors… stress theoretical or abstract analogies… whereas others focus on visual similarities.” (p. 919)

🤝 8. Configuration: Identification vs Juxtaposition

Epiphora (explicit “A is B”) vs Diaphora (juxtaposition, “Petals on a wet black bough”).

🧱 9. Dependence on Conceptual Systems

Metaphors may be linked to conceptual metaphors (e.g., LIFE IS A JOURNEY) or be entirely idiosyncratic.

“To the best of my knowledge, at least half of the most memorable literary metaphors are not [conceptual].” (p. 923)

🌐 10. Transference of Associated Field

Extent to which a metaphor transfers conceptual frameworks.

🚨 11. Degree of Deautomatization

How much the metaphor disrupts ordinary perception (cf. Shklovsky’s defamiliarization).

🔄 12. Symmetry of Predication

Is the metaphor reversible? (“Achilles is a lion” vs. “Lion is Achilles”).

“From the point of view of the status of the attribute… metaphors can vary from symmetrical… to asymmetrical.” (p. 926)


💬 Key Quotations with Citations

🟣 “It does not say and it does not hide, it intimates.” – Heraclitus, quoted by Davidson (p. 913)

🔵 “The pure eidetic concept of metaphor, like pure existence, is not an essence but only a field of possibilities.” (p. 927)

🟠 “Metaphor is a metaphor is a metaphor is a metaphor.” (p. 927)

🟢 “Like an elephant, metaphor is neither a rope, nor a trumpet or a pillar… but in a sense, it can become any of them.” (p. 927)

Theoretical Terms/Concepts in “Metaphor Revisited” by Dennis Sobolev
🔹 Concept/Term🧠 Explanation📚 Reference
Structure of IdentificationA formal procedure for recognizing metaphors, based on necessary and sufficient conditions such as logical contradiction or conceptual incongruity.Sobolev, p. 906–907
Structure of FunctioningFocuses on how metaphors operate cognitively and semantically, and their impact on readers — not just how they are recognized.Sobolev, p. 906
Necessary ConditionsAttributes that signal metaphorical usage: contradiction, incongruity, falsity, irrelevance, tautology, banality, etc.Sobolev, p. 907
Sufficient ConditionThe presence of similarity or resemblance — substantial or relational — between metaphorical terms.Sobolev, p. 909
Tripartite StructureMetaphor comprises: ① Frame (literal context), ② Figurative Term, and ③ Theme (subject).Sobolev, p. 905
Transference vs. InteractionTwo metaphor types: ① Mechanical attribute transference (e.g. “Achilles is a lion”) vs. ② Interpretive interaction (e.g. “Bill is a barn door”).Sobolev, p. 911–912
Truth vs. SuccessSome metaphors are judged by truth conditions (e.g. “Achilles is a lion”), others by success of semantic resonance (e.g. “Mind has mountains”).Sobolev, p. 913–914
Given vs. Produced SimilaritySome metaphors emphasize pre-existing resemblance; others create new similarities (especially in poetic or philosophical metaphors).Sobolev, p. 915–916
Metaphors of Creation vs. ElucidationMetaphors can either create new meaning (e.g. catachresis) or clarify existing concepts (e.g. “The president is a pig”).Sobolev, p. 917
Metaphors of Juxtaposition vs. IdentificationJuxtaposition involves implied comparison (diaphora); Identification uses explicit predication (“A is B”, or epiphora).Sobolev, p. 919–920
Explicit Designation vs. ReplacementSome metaphors name the subject clearly (e.g. “Achilles is a lion”); others imply it obliquely (e.g. “Greek lion frightened the enemies”).Sobolev, p. 921
Conceptual TransferenceMetaphors may rely on broader cultural or cognitive schema (e.g. LIFE IS A JOURNEY); others are isolated.Sobolev, p. 922–923
Degree of Associated Field TransferHow much of the source concept’s traits are transferred (e.g. from journey to life); varies from full mapping to isolated traits.Sobolev, p. 924
DeautomatizationThe extent
Contribution of “Metaphor Revisited” by Dennis Sobolev to Literary Theory/Theories

🔍 1. Structuralism & Post-Structuralism

  • Repositioning metaphor after the linguistic turn: Sobolev examines how metaphor functioned as a foundational unit in structuralist models (influenced by Jakobson), and why its significance declined under poststructuralism.

“Literary scholars had been working within the ‘literature as a language’ paradigm… metaphor as one of the two pivotal operations” (p. 903–904).

  • Critique of poststructural abandonment: Instead of discarding metaphor in poststructural thought, Sobolev argues that metaphor’s synthetic role in culture makes it even more important within heterogeneous interpretive paradigms.

“The significance of metaphor as a model must only grow… being one of the simplest and most exhaustively studied operations of synthesis” (p. 904).


🧠 2. Rhetorical Theory

  • Revives classical notions (e.g. Aristotle’s idea of resemblance) while critically reworking them through modern analytical logic.

“The sufficient condition… is similarity or resemblance” (p. 909).

  • Refines the dichotomy between tenor/vehicle (Richards) and focus/frame (Black) by introducing a tripartite model of metaphor (frame, figurative term, theme).

“This structure includes a ‘frame’… and a ‘theme’” (p. 905).


🧬 3. Cognitive Metaphor Theory

  • Nuanced critique of Lakoff & Johnson’s “conceptual metaphor” model: Sobolev challenges the idea that all metaphors derive from large conceptual mappings like LIFE IS A JOURNEY.

“Not every metaphor is based on conventional conceptual transference” (p. 923).

  • Introduces the degree of dependence on conceptual metaphors as one of several axes, making metaphor analysis more granular and context-specific.

“Most empirical metaphors are located somewhere in between” (p. 924).


🧪 4. Analytic Philosophy of Language

  • Engages with thinkers like Black, Davidson, Goodman, and Searle to show the limits of semantic reductionism in metaphor theory.

“To say that metaphor can be called ‘metaphor’ only if it was intended or interpreted as metaphor merely redirects the discussion” (p. 909).

  • Argues for pluralism over essentialism: metaphor is not reducible to a single model (e.g. interaction or resemblance), but is a field of structured variation.

“Metaphor is not a single unified structure… but a field of heterogeneous possibilities” (p. 905).


🎨 5. Poetics / Literary Stylistics

  • Clarifies poetic metaphor’s distinctiveness from everyday metaphor by mapping how poetic language resists conceptual flattening.

“The meaning of ‘crooked eclipses’ is irreducible to truth conditions… it makes the reader notice numerous similarities” (p. 914).

  • Introduces axes of metaphorical structure (e.g., interaction type, similarity type, conceptual scope), useful for stylistic and formal analysis of poetry (e.g., Hopkins, Shakespeare).

“Empirical metaphors are situated along the axis of metaphorical operation… ‘transference’ and ‘foregrounding’” (p. 913).


🌀 6. Hermeneutics

  • Separates “identification” from “functioning” to avoid interpretive circularity — enabling more precise metaphoric interpretation.

“It is insufficient to know how metaphors are identified in order to explain the essence of their functioning” (p. 906).

  • Expands hermeneutics of metaphor to include cultural competence, reader cognition, and semantic play across contexts.

“The person must be able to identify… conceptual incongruities and contextual irrelevance” (p. 910).


📏 7. Theory of Interpretation / Defamiliarization

  • Integrates Shklovsky’s “defamiliarization” into metaphor theory by defining a scale of deautomatization.

“Metaphors… draw attention to their conceptual basis” and can induce “rethinking” (p. 925).

  • Shows how even conventional metaphors (e.g., “he is gone”) can vary in deautomatizing power, especially in poetic use.

🧩 8. Semiotics and Pragmatics

  • Demonstrates that metaphor cannot be wholly reduced to semantics, pragmatics, or logic alone.

“Metaphors can be related to any and all of these spheres” (p. 908).

  • Introduces the multi-modal nature of metaphor—logical, semantic, and contextual—requiring interdisciplinary interpretation.

🧭 9. Typology and Classification

  • Develops a multi-axial typology of metaphor — 12 axes including:
    • Type of similarity (given vs. produced)
    • Metaphor’s symmetry
    • Degree of field transference
    • Modality (truth vs. success)

“Its space… structured by several independent axes… creates a possibility of hundreds of metaphorical structures” (p. 926).

Examples of Critiques Through “Metaphor Revisited” by Dennis Sobolev
Literary WorkMetaphorical ExampleType of Metaphor (Sobolev)Axes of InterpretationInterpretive Significance
William Shakespeare’s Julius Caesar“Let slip the dogs of war”🔁 Transference Metaphor🔹 Transference vs. Interaction🔹 Truth/Falsity Axis🔹 Configuration (Epiphora)Projects violence through animal metaphor; transposes aggression from warfare to bestial instinct, aligning with Sobolev’s notion of projecting “commonplaces.”
T. S. Eliot’s The Love Song of J. Alfred Prufrock“I should have been a pair of ragged claws”🔍 Foregrounding & Juxtaposition (Diaphora)🔹 Perceptual vs. Intelligible Similarity🔹 Juxtaposition🔹 DeautomatizationHighlights alienation and inaction through abstract-physical clash; metaphor resists paraphrase, affirming Sobolev’s view of metaphor as semantic synthesis.
Emily Dickinson’s Because I could not stop for Death“Because I could not stop for Death – He kindly stopped for me”🔄 Catachresis & Identification Metaphor🔹 Creation vs. Elucidation🔹 Conceptual Transference🔹 Symmetry AxisDeath personified as a courteous figure shows metaphor’s power to create abstract embodiment, consistent with Sobolev’s creation-based axis and interactional structure.
Sylvia Plath’s Lady Lazarus“Out of the ash / I rise with my red hair”🔥 Interaction-Based Mythical Metaphor🔹 Given vs. Produced Similarity🔹 Transference of Associated Field🔹 DefamiliarizationMerges biblical, mythical, and modern imagery to reconstruct trauma and identity, showing metaphor’s cultural heterogeneity and high deautomatization, per Sobolev.
Criticism Against “Metaphor Revisited” by Dennis Sobolev

🧩 Over-Systematization of Metaphor

  • Sobolev’s framework, while comprehensive, risks over-categorizing metaphor into rigid axes and parameters.
  • The multiplicity of axes (at least 12) may obscure rather than clarify how metaphors operate in real literary contexts.
  • Critique: Literature’s metaphoric fluidity may not fit easily into such a formalized matrix of analysis.

🔁 Underrepresentation of Reader-Response

  • Sobolev places heavy emphasis on formal identification and theoretical function, but pays insufficient attention to reader variation in metaphor interpretation.
  • Critique: Cognitive and affective responses of diverse readers are minimized in favor of structural analysis.

🤔 Ambiguity in Practical Application

  • Despite theoretical richness, the application of the 12-axis model can be challenging and inconsistent across varied texts.
  • Critique: The model may be more useful as an abstract heuristic than a consistently applicable analytical tool in literary criticism.

🧠 Critique of Similarity as a “Sufficient Condition”

  • Sobolev restores similarity (resemblance) as the core identifying principle of metaphor.
  • Critics (e.g., Goodman, Davidson) argue this reinstates a problematic and reductive notion, especially when metaphor creates rather than reflects similarity.
  • Critique: The assumption that similarity is always central can be questioned for novel or experimental metaphors.

🔄 Minimal Engagement with Postmodern and Deconstructive Theories

  • While Sobolev acknowledges poststructuralist shifts, he largely reinstates a formalist lens on metaphor.
  • Critique: This neglects deconstructive insights on metaphor’s instability, undecidability, and rhetorical play (e.g., Derrida’s view of metaphor as différance).

🔍 Neglect of Non-Western and Cross-Cultural Metaphor Traditions

  • The essay primarily engages with European and Anglo-American metaphor theory (Aristotle, Black, Ricoeur, Lakoff).
  • Critique: Fails to account for cross-cultural metaphor paradigms or literary traditions beyond the Western canon.

🧪 Scientific vs. Literary Metaphors Not Fully Resolved

  • Sobolev discusses scientific metaphors but leaves unclear boundaries between literal scientific models and literary metaphorical imagination.
  • Critique: Risks conflating technical analogy with poetic metaphor, weakening analytical distinction.

🧵 Complexity May Undermine Usability

  • The high abstraction and technical vocabulary (e.g., “metaphors of juxtaposition,” “defamiliarization axis”) may alienate readers not deeply familiar with rhetorical theory.
  • Critique: Could benefit from clearer integration of concrete literary examples earlier in the essay.
Representative Quotations from “Metaphor Revisited” by Dennis Sobolev with Explanation
🔖 Quotation💡 Explanation
“Metaphor… is not a single unified structure, but rather a field of heterogeneous possibilities.” (p. 904)Sobolev redefines metaphor not as a fixed linguistic form but as a multiplicity of interacting structures, challenging essentialist views.
“There is an essential difference between these questions [identification vs. functioning], and the existence of an answer to the former does not guarantee that there must also exist an answer to the latter.” (p. 906)Distinguishes between the structure of identification (how we recognize a metaphor) and the structure of functioning (how it operates), emphasizing the complexity of metaphor.
“The sufficient condition of the identification of metaphor has been widely known since Aristotle: this is ‘similarity’ or ‘resemblance.’” (p. 909)Revisits and reaffirms Aristotle’s classical idea that metaphor depends on perceived similarity, pushing back against modern skepticism.
“Interaction between the terms is not symmetrical… it results in the foregrounding of certain attributes of the primary term.” (p. 913)Challenges simplistic models by suggesting metaphor involves asymmetric cognitive projection—the secondary term reshapes how we perceive the primary one.
“Some metaphors can be true or false… others can only be successful or unsuccessful.” (p. 914)Introduces the idea that metaphors should be evaluated not only on truth value but also on communicative success, drawing on Austin’s speech act theory.
“The mind has mountains” is neither true nor false… but the interaction between its terms is definitely successful.” (p. 915)Uses poetic metaphor to demonstrate how successfulness, not literal truth, often defines metaphorical power.
“Metaphor always foregrounds similarity, although this
Suggested Readings: “Metaphor Revisited” by Dennis Sobolev
  1. Sobolev, Dennis. “Metaphor Revisited.” New Literary History, vol. 39, no. 4, 2008, pp. 903–29. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/20533122. Accessed 13 May 2025.
  2. MacCormac, Earl R. “Metaphor Revisited.” The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, vol. 30, no. 2, 1971, pp. 239–50. JSTOR, https://doi.org/10.2307/429543. Accessed 13 May 2025.
  3. Glicksohn, Joseph, and Chanita Goodblatt. “Metaphor and Gestalt: Interaction Theory Revisited.” Poetics Today, vol. 14, no. 1, 1993, pp. 83–97. JSTOR, https://doi.org/10.2307/1773141. Accessed 13 May 2025.
  4. “Metaphor [Bibliography].” Newsletter: Rhetoric Society of America, vol. 4, no. 3, 1974, pp. 5–13. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/3885137. Accessed 13 May 2025.

“Metaphor Comprehension: What Makes a Metaphor Difficult to Understand?” by Walter Kintsch & Anita R. Bowles: Summary and Critique

“Metaphor Comprehension: What Makes a Metaphor Difficult to Understand?” by Walter Kintsch and Anita R. Bowles first appeared in Metaphor and Symbol in 2002 (Vol. 17, Issue 4, pp. 249–262), published by Psychology Press.

"Metaphor Comprehension: What Makes a Metaphor Difficult to Understand?" by Walter Kintsch & Anita R. Bowles: Summary and Critique
Introduction: “Metaphor Comprehension: What Makes a Metaphor Difficult to Understand?” by Walter Kintsch & Anita R. Bowles

“Metaphor Comprehension: What Makes a Metaphor Difficult to Understand?” by Walter Kintsch and Anita R. Bowles first appeared in Metaphor and Symbol in 2002 (Vol. 17, Issue 4, pp. 249–262), published by Psychology Press. This pivotal article investigates the cognitive mechanisms underpinning metaphor comprehension, challenging the traditional view that metaphors inherently require a qualitatively different processing strategy than literal language. Through empirical analysis and computational modeling, the authors demonstrate that metaphors of the form NOUN1 is a NOUN2 are often understood using the same basic cognitive strategies applied to literal sentences. Central to their study is the use of Latent Semantic Analysis (LSA), a method for modeling meaning in high-dimensional semantic space, and the predication model, which adjusts the vector of a predicate based on its argument to yield context-sensitive interpretations. Their findings reveal that metaphor comprehension difficulty is not significantly related to the surface semantic similarity between the metaphor’s terms, but rather to the availability of shared semantic features that link the metaphor’s topic and vehicle. Importantly, both human participants and the computational model showed similar patterns in interpreting metaphors: strong agreement and coherence for easy metaphors, and more diverse yet non-random responses for difficult ones. This work is significant in literary theory and cognitive linguistics as it offers a formal, computable framework to explain metaphor comprehension, moving beyond intuitive or purely analogical models. It aligns with, and extends, the class-inclusion theory of Glucksberg (1998) and supports a semantic-constraint-based view of comprehension that blurs the boundaries between literal and figurative language processing.

Summary of “Metaphor Comprehension: What Makes a Metaphor Difficult to Understand?” by Walter Kintsch & Anita R. Bowles

🔷 1. Metaphors and Literal Language: No Special Processing Required

  • People process metaphors similarly to literal sentences in most cases.
  • It does not appear that metaphor comprehension first involves an attempt at literal comprehension and, when that fails, a metaphoric reinterpretation❞ (Kintsch & Bowles, 2002, p. 249).
  • Ordinary metaphors are usually automatically understood, without cognitive overload.
  • 🔍 This finding challenges traditional theories that treat metaphor as inherently more complex than literal language.

🔶 2. What Makes a Metaphor Difficult? It’s Not What You Think

  • Difficulty is not due to:
    • Semantic distance between words 🔁
    • Word frequency or vector length 🧮
  • It is not the case that easy understanding requires a preexisting global relation between the two terms❞ (p. 258).
  • Rather, it depends on whether shared semantic neighbors can be found between topic and vehicle.
  • Metaphors are easy to process if the argument has a good match among the close neighbors of the predicate❞ (p. 257).

🟣 3. Latent Semantic Analysis (LSA): Mapping Meaning in Space

  • Words are represented as vectors in a 300-dimensional semantic space.
  • Meaning is a position in this huge semantic space… we can calculate how close or far apart two vectors are❞ (p. 250).
  • Sentence meaning is computed by adding vectors, allowing computational modeling of metaphor comprehension.

🟢 4. The Predication Model: Adding Context to Semantics

  • The predication algorithm modifies predicate vectors based on context (argument word).
  • For example, 🦈 “My lawyer is a shark” highlights “aggressive” traits of “shark,” not the literal ones.
  • The meaning of the predicate is a shark is very different from shark in isolation❞ (p. 251).
  • This is how LSA simulates human-like metaphor interpretation.

🔴 5. Easy vs. Difficult Metaphors: Experimental Evidence

  • Participants rated 13 metaphors as easy and 13 as difficult.
  • High agreement on easy metaphors (48% modal agreement) vs. low on difficult ones (21%).
  • Even “nonsense” metaphors triggered non-random interpretations.
  • Even for what one might regard as pure nonsense, there was still a considerable level of agreement❞ (p. 254).

🔵 6. Model Validation: Matching Human Responses

  • LSA-predicated vectors closely matched participant-generated interpretations.
  • For both easy and difficult metaphors, the average cosine similarity between model and human responses was ≈ 0.51.
  • For difficult metaphors, responses were more varied, but the model produced a vector that was just as close to these varied responses❞ (p. 258).

🟡 7. Cognitive Consistency: Even Diffuse Responses Make Sense

  • The model does not break down on difficult metaphors—it generates diffuse but coherent meanings.
  • The semantic structure provided a tight constraint for easy metaphors, and only a loose one for hard metaphors❞ (p. 258).
  • Human and model interpretations converge because of shared semantic constraints.

🟤 8. Theoretical Contributions to Literary and Linguistic Theory

  • Supports Glucksberg’s class-inclusion model and Frisson & Pickering’s underspecification model.
  • Offers a computational realization of metaphor interpretation mechanisms in cognitive science.
  • We also claim that the results presented here show that LSA provides a useful basis for a psychological theory of meaning❞ (p. 259).

🔺 9. Key Insight: Local Connections Trump Global Similarity

  • Metaphors work not by global similarity, but by activating shared contextual features.
  • Lawyer and shark are orthogonal… but there are aspects—like vicious or mean—that link the two❞ (p. 258).

Theoretical Terms/Concepts in “Metaphor Comprehension: What Makes a Metaphor Difficult to Understand?” by Walter Kintsch & Anita R. Bowles

🌐 TermExplanationReference from the Article
🧠 Latent Semantic Analysis (LSA)A computational method for deriving the meaning of words and texts by placing them in a high-dimensional semantic space based on word co-occurrence.Words, sentences, and texts are represented as vectors in this space…we can calculate how close or far apart two vectors are in this semantic space” (p. 250).
📐 Semantic SpaceA high-dimensional vector space (typically 300–400 dimensions) used to represent meanings of words and their relationships.Semantic maps—spaces—of 300 to 400 dimensions yield results that are most closely aligned with human judgments” (p. 250).
🧠 Predication AlgorithmA model that adjusts the vector of a predicate based on contextual features derived from its argument to generate a context-sensitive meaning.The meaning of the predicate is modified to generate a contextually appropriate sense of the word” (p. 251).
🌐 Argument and PredicateIn NOUN1 IS A NOUN2 metaphors, NOUN1 is the argument (topic), and NOUN2 is the predicate (vehicle/metaphor source).NOUN1 is called the argument (A) and NOUN2 is called the predicate (P)” (Appendix, p. 260).
🧠 Vector Cosine SimilarityA measure used in LSA to determine semantic similarity between concepts; ranges from –1 (opposite) to +1 (identical).The cosine between highly similar vectors is close to +1, whereas unrelated vectors have a cosine close to zero” (p. 251).
📐 Centroid (Vector Sum)The average of several vectors; used to represent the collective meaning of a sentence or group of words.Sentence meanings are computed as the sum of the words, irrespective of their syntactic structure” (p. 250).
🌐 Semantic NeighborhoodA group of vectors (words) that are closest in meaning to a given vector in the LSA space.It constructs the semantic neighborhood of the predicate…most closely related to the predicate” (p. 251).
🧠 Constraint Satisfaction ProcessA cognitive mechanism in the predication model that integrates the predicate’s neighborhood with the argument to derive meaning.Uses a constraint satisfaction process to integrate this neighborhood with the argument” (p. 251).
📐 Spreading ActivationA process by which activation spreads through a network to identify most relevant semantic neighbors for metaphor interpretation.Activation is spread in that network…The most strongly activated neighbors of P will be used to modify P” (p. 260).
🌐 Metaphoric Superordinate CategoriesAbstract categories created by metaphors that go beyond literal taxonomies (e.g., “shark” becoming a category of “vicious professionals”).The notion of generating metaphorical superordinate categories can be operationalized” (p. 252).
Contribution of “Metaphor Comprehension: What Makes a Metaphor Difficult to Understand?” by Walter Kintsch & Anita R. Bowles to Literary Theory/Theories

🧠 Contribution to Cognitive Literary Theory

  • Supports the view that metaphor comprehension uses general cognitive processes.
    ↳ The article aligns with the notion that metaphors are understood in ways similar to literal sentences, challenging the assumption that metaphor requires unique interpretive faculties.

There exists a considerable and convincing body of research…that indicates that people understand metaphors in much the same way they understand literal sentences” (p. 249).

  • Uses cognitive modeling (LSA and predication) to simulate metaphor interpretation.
    ↳ Introduces a formal, empirically tested model showing how meaning emerges through contextual semantic alignment, which cognitive literary theorists find central to interpretive modeling.

We describe a model of text comprehension…simulate the computations involved, and evaluate the model empirically” (p. 250).


🧬 Contribution to Formalist and Structuralist Theories

  • Operationalizes metaphor using structural linguistic units (NOUN1 IS A NOUN2).
    ↳ The study isolates and systematizes metaphor into a rigid syntactic structure, echoing formalist interests in text-intrinsic form and structure.

Each stimulus sentence was a metaphorical statement of the NOUN1 IS A NOUN2” (p. 253).

  • Examines metaphoric meaning independently of reader emotion or authorial intent.
    ↳ The focus on semantic proximity, not subjective interpretation, aligns with structuralist ideals of objectivity in literary analysis.

The sentence vector should be more closely related to the set of interpretations generated by human comprehenders than to the individual words of the sentence” (p. 252).


🧪 Contribution to Empirical Literary Studies

  • Integrates experimental data into literary interpretation.
    ↳ The study used participant data and cosine-based metrics to evaluate metaphor difficulty, marking a shift from speculative literary criticism to quantifiable methods.

Difficulty ratings ranged from 1.29…to 4.21…responses were more coherent for easy items” (p. 254).

  • Establishes reproducibility and statistical grounding in interpretive variation.
    ↳ Demonstrates that metaphor comprehension can be empirically tested, supporting efforts in empirical literary studies to systematize interpretation.

The difference between the coherence of easy items and difficult items was statistically significant, t(24) = 4.38, p < .01” (p. 254).


🧭 Contribution to Reader-Response Theory

  • Explores interpretive variance among readers.
    ↳ The study highlights how reader agreement decreases with metaphor difficulty, resonating with reader-response theory’s emphasis on individual interpretation.

Faced with items such as ‘Happiness is a ditch’…people didn’t just give up but found some interpretation” (p. 254).

  • Suggests that comprehension is shaped by semantic constraints, not just subjective imagination.
    ↳ Even for difficult metaphors, interpretations were not random but guided by the latent semantic structure, refining the reader-response notion of subjective freedom.

Even though interpretations are diffuse…they are not random. This consistency…may simply reflect word-based constraints” (p. 258).


🧠📐 Contribution to Conceptual Metaphor Theory (Lakoff & Johnson)

  • Empirically supports metaphor as a cognitive mapping process.
    ↳ The study shows how metaphors create conceptual relationships by adjusting predicate meanings via contextually relevant features.

The meaning of the predicate is modified to generate a contextually appropriate sense of the word” (p. 251).

  • Adds computational rigor to conceptual blending.
    ↳ By modeling how metaphorical understanding emerges through a network of semantic connections, it extends the conceptual metaphor theory into testable, mechanistic terms.

The vector computed by the model is equally close to that average of easy and difficult items” (p. 255).


⚙️ Contribution to Computational Literary Theory

  • Demonstrates how semantic computation can approximate human interpretation.
    ↳ LSA and the predication model simulate how people derive meaning from metaphor, advancing computational approaches to literary meaning.

The model vector nevertheless captures the variety of responses produced by the participants” (p. 257).

  • Presents a fully realized computational theory of meaning.
    ↳ Unlike traditional metaphor theories, this model allows for quantification and algorithmic generation of interpretation, moving toward AI-assisted literary analysis.

Our model is a fully realized, computational theory” (p. 252).

Examples of Critiques Through “Metaphor Comprehension: What Makes a Metaphor Difficult to Understand?” by Walter Kintsch & Anita R. Bowles
📚 Literary Work🔍 Example Metaphor from the Work🧠 Interpretive Analysis (Kintsch & Bowles Lens)️ Critique Based on Model
🦁 The Old Man and the Sea – Ernest Hemingway“The fish is my brother.”Metaphor follows the NOUN1 IS A NOUN2 form; argument = fish, predicate = brother. The predication model would identify features like shared struggle, respect, kinship as vectors connecting fish and brother.✅ Easy metaphor: Participants (readers) would likely converge on the emotional and symbolic kinship. High cosine values suggest semantic proximity once context is integrated. Strong coherence.
🦇 Wuthering Heights – Emily Brontë“Whatever our souls are made of, his and mine are the same.”Though syntactically complex, metaphor relies on blending abstract noun (souls) with identity sameness. The metaphor is indirect, so coherence may vary. Vector representations of souls, same, and his/mine create a loose semantic field.⚠️ Moderately difficult: Metaphoric interpretation is diffuse; LSA may struggle due to abstraction and lack of direct predicates. Requires structural alignment (Gentner & Bowdle).
🔥 The Waste Land – T. S. Eliot“April is the cruellest month.”NOUN1 IS NOUN2 metaphor with April (argument) and cruellest month (predicate). Contradicts conventional associations (spring with renewal). Model seeks shared neighbors between April and cruelty.❌ Difficult metaphor: Low baseline similarity; predication model generates vague and varied responses. Semantic coherence weak due to conflicting cultural frames. Low cosine match.
🐍 Macbeth – William Shakespeare“Look like the innocent flower, but be the serpent under’t.”Implicit dual metaphor. Flower and serpent are semantic opposites. The model would modify serpent through context (deception, hidden danger) and apply it to Macbeth’s intentions.✅ Effective metaphor: Though figurative, structure aids LSA processing. High activation of relevant neighbors (e.g., danger, mask). Moderate difficulty but high interpretive coherence.
Criticism Against “Metaphor Comprehension: What Makes a Metaphor Difficult to Understand?” by Walter Kintsch & Anita R. Bowles

🔄 Overreliance on Computational Models

  • The study heavily depends on Latent Semantic Analysis (LSA) and the predication algorithm, which treat language geometrically.
  • Critics argue this abstracts away cognitive nuance and fails to account for non-semantic cues such as pragmatics, cultural knowledge, or emotional tone.
  • ❝ “Meaning is reduced to vector math, bypassing richer interpretive dynamics involved in actual reading.” (cf. Gentner & Bowdle, 2001)

📏 Neglect of Syntax and Word Order

  • LSA used in the model ignores syntactic structure, computing sentence meaning via summation of word vectors regardless of grammar.
  • This approach may oversimplify how meaning is constructed, especially for metaphors relying on syntax-dependent effects.
  • Kintsch admits: “Such a procedure neglects important, meaning-relevant information that is contained in word order and syntax.” (p. 250)

🧩 Limited Scope of Metaphor Types

  • The study is restricted to simple nominal metaphors (NOUN1 IS A NOUN2), excluding:
    • Verbal metaphors
    • Extended metaphors
    • Metaphors embedded in narrative discourse
  • This makes the model less generalizable to rich literary or philosophical texts with layered figurative complexity.

🤖 Assumption of Universal Processing

  • The model assumes metaphor comprehension is uniform across individuals, whereas real readers vary due to:
    • Background knowledge
    • Personal associations
    • Linguistic and cultural exposure
  • Kintsch & Bowles acknowledge interpretive variation but still evaluate model success by group-level averages, masking individuality.

🔍 Lack of Qualitative Interpretive Depth

  • The study’s quantitative focus on cosine similarity lacks insight into interpretive depth, such as:
    • Moral connotation
    • Intertextual echoes
    • Aesthetic or rhetorical effect
  • The model evaluates metaphor meaning only by statistical coherence, not by literary or emotional richness.

🧪 Artificial Experimental Context

  • Participants completed sentence frames and gave difficulty ratings in a lab setting with isolated metaphors.
  • Critics may question ecological validity—metaphors in real texts are processed within broader narrative, emotional, and discursive contexts.

🧠 Cognitive Economy Not Fully Addressed

  • The model doesn’t sufficiently address cognitive economy principles, such as why:
    • Some metaphors are retained and others forgotten
    • Some metaphors “click” quickly while others are puzzling or evocative
  • The authors touch on this via coherence scores, but the deeper cognitive prioritization mechanisms remain underexplored.

🧬 Ambiguity in Defining “Difficulty”

  • The metric for what makes a metaphor “difficult” is partly subjective, relying on participant self-ratings and coherence calculations.
  • This leaves room for ambiguity in distinguishing between semantic novelty, conceptual mismatch, and reader confusion.
Representative Quotations from “Metaphor Comprehension: What Makes a Metaphor Difficult to Understand?” by Walter Kintsch & Anita R. Bowles with Explanation
QuotationExplanation
“People understand metaphors in much the same way they understand literal sentences.” (p. 249)Challenges the view that metaphor processing is fundamentally different; suggests metaphor comprehension is a natural language process.
“The meaning of a word, sentence, or text is given by the set of relations between it and everything else that is known.” (p. 250)Reflects the core idea behind Latent Semantic Analysis (LSA) – meaning is relational, not fixed.
“Metaphors are not difficult because their argument and predicate terms are unrelated overall.” (p. 256)Refutes the intuition that semantic distance alone determines difficulty in metaphor comprehension.
“The model vector is equally close to the average of easy and the average of difficult items.” (p. 255)Shows that the computational model treats both metaphor types similarly in vector space despite participant differences.
“Some link is found between topic and vehicle, even though the two may be unrelated overall.” (p. 258)Highlights the model’s strength in identifying subtle, context-sensitive links between unrelated terms in metaphors.
“The model produced a vector that was just as close to these varied responses as it was to the generally agreed-upon interpretation of a good metaphor.” (p. 258)Emphasizes that the model handles ambiguity effectively, mimicking human flexibility in metaphor interpretation.
“Faced with the seemingly impossible task of finding an interpretation for such metaphors, people did not give up.” (p. 258)Demonstrates human resilience and interpretative creativity even in difficult metaphorical constructions.
“Generating context-sensitive word senses does not always produce dramatic results.” (p. 251)Acknowledges that not all metaphors lead to strong reinterpretations; some may resemble literal interpretations.
“The semantic structure provided a tight constraint for easy metaphors, and only a loose one for hard metaphors.” (p. 258)Suggests semantic coherence plays a central role in determining perceived metaphor difficulty.
“Theories of metaphor comprehension have traditionally been informal.” (p. 258)Justifies the importance of formal, computational models like LSA to bring precision to metaphor theory.
Suggested Readings: “Metaphor Comprehension: What Makes a Metaphor Difficult to Understand?” by Walter Kintsch & Anita R. Bowles
  1. Kittay, Eva Feder. “Woman as Metaphor.” Hypatia, vol. 3, no. 2, 1988, pp. 63–86. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/3809952. Accessed 12 May 2025.
  2. Gibbs, Raymond W. “When Is Metaphor? The Idea of Understanding in Theories of Metaphor.” Poetics Today, vol. 13, no. 4, 1992, pp. 575–606. JSTOR, https://doi.org/10.2307/1773290. Accessed 12 May 2025.
  3. BLACK, Max. “More about Metaphor.” Dialectica, vol. 31, no. 3/4, 1977, pp. 431–57. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/42969757. Accessed 12 May 2025.
  4. Miller, Eugene F. “Metaphor and Political Knowledge.” The American Political Science Review, vol. 73, no. 1, 1979, pp. 155–70. JSTOR, https://doi.org/10.2307/1954738. Accessed 12 May 2025.
  5. Wearing, Catherine. “Metaphor, Idiom, and Pretense.” Noûs, vol. 46, no. 3, 2012, pp. 499–524. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/41682624. Accessed 12 May 2025.

“Metaphor in Prophetic Literature” by Else K. Holt: Summary and Critique

“Metaphor in Prophetic Literature” by Else K. Holt first appeared in Scandinavian Journal of the Old Testament: An International Journal of Nordic Theology in 2003 (Vol. 17, No. 1, pp. 3–6), published by Routledge.

"Metaphor in Prophetic Literature" by Else K. Holt: Summary and Critique
Introduction: “Metaphor in Prophetic Literature” by Else K. Holt

“Metaphor in Prophetic Literature” by Else K. Holt first appeared in Scandinavian Journal of the Old Testament: An International Journal of Nordic Theology in 2003 (Vol. 17, No. 1, pp. 3–6), published by Routledge. The article foregrounds the centrality of metaphor in understanding Old Testament prophetic texts, arguing that metaphors are not mere rhetorical flourishes but essential instruments for articulating divine-human relationships. Holt draws attention to the theological and interpretive significance of metaphor, noting its irreplaceable role when speaking of God—the “illusive, holy figure”—who resists definitive capture by plain language, as echoed in Walter Brueggemann’s reflections. She critiques historical-critical methods for demythologizing metaphoric language, thus diminishing the semantic richness of biblical texts. The article also introduces a collection of conference papers from the 2001 International Meeting of the Society of Biblical Literature, exploring metaphor theory and its application to the Book of Jeremiah. Contributions by scholars like Kirsten Nielsen and Antje Labahn expand on metaphor’s ideological weight and intertextual dynamics, while others, such as A.R. Pete Diamond and Pierre van Hecke, delve into metaphorical shifts and tensions in Jeremiah’s oracles. Holt’s editorial preface underscores how metaphors not only reflect but actively shape theological meaning, advocating for continued, rigorous metaphor studies within biblical scholarship and literary theory.

Summary of “Metaphor in Prophetic Literature” by Else K. Holt

🕊️ 1. Metaphor as a Theological Necessity

“When we talk about God, the absolute otherness, we have to talk tentatively, that is: in metaphor” (© Holt 2003, p. 3).
💡 Meaning: Metaphors are not optional in prophetic literature—they are essential because human language is inadequate for directly describing the divine.


⚖️ 2. Critique of Reductionism in Traditional Exegesis

“Exegetes… have translated this imagery into plain language… the texts have been demythologised” (© Holt 2003, p. 4).
🧠 Insight: Historical-critical methods often flatten rich, symbolic language, reducing theological depth and eliminating mystery.


🔄 3. Postmodern Responsibility: Avoiding Old Mistakes

“Post-modern exegetes should be careful not to transmit [reductionism]… to literary or reader-oriented study” (© Holt 2003, p. 4).
🔍 Takeaway: Even new approaches must preserve the semantic and poetic power of metaphor instead of simplifying it for clarity.


🧩 4. Bridging Theory and Practice in Metaphor Studies

“Papers on metaphor theory were read after the papers on the use of metaphor… but it has been natural to present… method before practice” (© Holt 2003, p. 4).
📚 Context: Holt introduces a volume combining theoretical frameworks with applied exegesis, especially focused on Jeremiah.


💥 5. Metaphors as Ideological Weapons

“Metaphors are not as harmless as they may seem… metaphors are often weapons in ideological wars” (© Nielsen, in Holt 2003, p. 5).
⚔️ Implication: Metaphors shape belief systems and power relations; their use can reinforce or subvert dominant ideologies.


🔗 6. Intertextual Webs of Meaning

“Texts are not islands… metaphors function as markers in such networks” (© Nielsen, in Holt 2003, p. 5).
🕸️ Understanding: Metaphors link scriptures across books, eras, and themes, guiding theological interpretations and memory.


👁️ 7. Reader-Dependent Metaphorical Meaning

“A metaphor… creates a sense of meaning… between the text and its reader” (© Labahn, in Holt 2003, p. 5).
🧬 Interpretation: Each reading reactivates and reshapes metaphorical meaning, showing the living dynamic between scripture and audience.


🔃 8. Recycled Tropes and Theological Reversals

“Both doom and hope dispossess and repossess rights to the myth of YHWH and Israel” (© Diamond, in Holt 2003, p. 6).
🔄 Effect: Metaphors recur throughout Jeremiah with reversed meanings—symbolizing shifts in divine judgment and restoration.


📜 9. Wisdom Sayings as Metaphorical Frameworks

“A wisdom saying… with a moral code included, or: a metaphor” (© Becking, in Holt 2003, p. 6).
📖 Layer: Proverbs like Jeremiah 31:29 operate metaphorically, reflecting collective theological insights and moral codes.


🐑🦁 10. Shifting Metaphors in Jeremiah’s Babylon Oracle

“Israel… restored… Babylon… turned into sheep… destroyed by God” (© van Hecke, in Holt 2003, p. 6).
🎭 Drama: Pastoral metaphors illustrate dramatic role reversals—God as shepherd or predator depending on justice and judgment.


🌟 11. Call for Ongoing Metaphor-Centered Exegesis

“Metaphor will remain in the centre of our exegetical attention” (© van Hecke, in Holt 2003, p. 6).
🧭 Vision: The article and volume advocate for metaphor to remain central in biblical interpretation and theological scholarship.

Theoretical Terms/Concepts in “Metaphor in Prophetic Literature” by Else K. Holt
🌐 Term/Concept📘 Explanation📝 Reference / Quotation
🔮 MetaphorA figurative expression used to speak about the divine, offering layers of meaning that cannot be reduced to plain language.“When we talk about God… we have to talk tentatively, that is: in metaphor” (© Holt 2003, p. 3).
🧠 ReductionismThe oversimplification of metaphorical or poetic language into plain, literal interpretation, often seen in historical-critical methods.“Exegetes… have translated this imagery into plain language… the texts have been demythologised” (© Holt 2003, p. 4).
🛠️ Historical-Critical MethodA traditional scholarly approach focusing on authorial intent, historical context, and literal meanings—critiqued for flattening metaphors.“Reductionism has been one of the great disadvantages of the historical-critical methods” (© Holt 2003, p. 4).
🔁 Postmodern ExegesisA more recent interpretive approach that engages reader-response and literary theory, encouraged to resist repeating reductionist tendencies.“Post-modern exegetes should be careful not to transmit [reductionism]…” (© Holt 2003, p. 4).
🎭 Performative FunctionThe idea that metaphors do something—they produce theological meaning and emotional effect in their context.“A metaphor… creates a sense of meaning… between the text and its reader” (© Labahn, in Holt 2003, p. 5).
⚔️ Ideological CriticismAn approach that sees metaphors as tools or weapons within ideological and theological conflicts.“Metaphors are often weapons in ideological wars” (© Nielsen, in Holt 2003, p. 5).
🔗 IntertextualityThe relationship between biblical texts, where metaphors act as recurring symbols across different books and historical contexts.“Metaphors function as markers in such networks [of intertextuality]” (© Nielsen, in Holt 2003, p. 5).
🧬 Semantic SpaceThe range of meanings a metaphor can evoke; narrowing this space through literalization limits interpretive richness.“The exegete… reduce[s] the text’s semantic space” (© Holt 2003, p. 4).
📚 Masal (משל)A wisdom saying or proverb with metaphorical implications and moral instruction, as used in prophetic literature.“A wisdom saying… with a moral code included, or: a metaphor” (© Becking, in Holt 2003, p. 6).
🔄 Metaphorical ShiftThe transformation or reapplication of metaphors over time or within a single text, revealing evolving meanings.“Israel… restored… Babylon… turned into sheep” (© van Hecke, in Holt 2003, p. 6).
Contribution of “Metaphor in Prophetic Literature” by Else K. Holt to Literary Theory/Theories

📖 1. Reader-Response Theory

“A metaphor… creates a sense of meaning… between the text and its reader” (© Labahn, in Holt 2003, p. 5).

🔸 Contribution:
Holt, particularly through the contributions in the volume she introduces, supports the reader-response perspective by emphasizing that metaphorical meaning is not fixed but dynamically constructed in the interpretive act between text and reader.

🔍 Impact:
The article affirms the reader’s role in meaning-making, highlighting how metaphors come alive differently for each audience and context — a core principle of reader-response theory.


🧠 2. Poststructuralism & Deconstruction

“Metaphors are not as harmless as they may seem… metaphors are often weapons in ideological wars” (© Nielsen, in Holt 2003, p. 5).

🔸 Contribution:
By illustrating how metaphors conceal power structures and multiple meanings, the article aligns with poststructuralist and deconstructionist thought, which sees texts as unstable and filled with ideological undercurrents.

🧩 Impact:
The instability and polysemy of metaphor echo Derridean insights — language doesn’t simply reflect meaning; it produces and displaces it.


📚 3. Intertextuality (Kristeva/Bakhtin)

“Texts are not islands… metaphors function as markers in such networks” (© Nielsen, in Holt 2003, p. 5).

🔸 Contribution:
The article foregrounds intertextuality by demonstrating how metaphors link prophetic texts across the canon (e.g., “Daughter of Zion” from Isaiah to Lamentations), embodying shared and evolving theological narratives.

🔗 Impact:
This strengthens the understanding of the Bible as a dialogical text network, with metaphors acting as relational bridges across literary and theological traditions.


🎭 4. Performance Theory

“The rhetorical performance arena of the literary construct (the Book of) Jeremiah” (© Diamond, in Holt 2003, p. 6).

🔸 Contribution:
Holt’s collection, especially through Diamond’s article, applies performance theory by treating the prophetic text as a staged drama of theological and ideological tensions enacted through metaphor.

🗣️ Impact:
This dramatized reading of metaphor supports literary theory that emphasizes how texts operate performatively — enacting meaning rather than just stating it.


⚔️ 5. Ideological Criticism / Cultural Criticism

“What is needed is… responsible exegesis… metaphors are often weapons in ideological wars” (© Nielsen, in Holt 2003, p. 5).

🔸 Contribution:
By stressing the ideological power of metaphor, Holt links biblical literature to cultural criticism and ideological theory, urging interpreters to see metaphors as vehicles of social and political meaning.

🚨 Impact:
This perspective aligns with Marxist and feminist literary theories, which interpret texts as participating in ideological systems of domination, resistance, and negotiation.


🧰 6. Literary Hermeneutics

“Exegetes… have demythologised… the texts… [reducing] the text’s semantic space” (© Holt 2003, p. 4).

🔸 Contribution:
Holt contributes to hermeneutical theory by emphasizing that metaphor opens, rather than closes, interpretive possibilities. She cautions against rigid literalism and advocates for openness to layered meaning.

🌀 Impact:
This view supports philosophical hermeneutics (e.g., Gadamer), where understanding involves openness to the text’s “otherness” and metaphor becomes a gateway to dialogue.


📜 7. Biblical Literary Criticism

“This volume is intended to add a little to the fulfilment of that wish [keeping metaphor central]” (© van Hecke, in Holt 2003, p. 6).

🔸 Contribution:
The article advances biblical literary criticism by urging scholars to read prophetic texts not as static historical documents but as rich literary creations shaped by symbolic logic and theological imagination.

📖 Impact:
It reframes prophecy as literary art — full of poetic structure, metaphorical density, and narrative strategy — aligning biblical studies more closely with broader literary theory.

Examples of Critiques Through “Metaphor in Prophetic Literature” by Else K. Holt
📚 Literary Work🔍 Critique Through Holt’s Metaphor Theory Key Metaphor(s) Analyzed📌 Symbolic Insight
🏛 The Book of JeremiahHolt’s framework reveals how metaphor operates as both theological performance and ideological contest. Metaphors such as “Daughter Zion” and “YHWH as predator/shepherd” shift across contexts to reflect divine judgment, grief, and restoration.🕊 Daughter of Zion, 🐑 Sheep, 🦁 Lion⚔️ Metaphors are rhetorical weapons in divine-human struggle and prophetic messaging (© Holt 2003, p. 6).
🏙 LamentationsUsing Holt’s intertextual lens, metaphors of desolation in Lamentations echo and reverse the hopeful Zion theology of Isaiah. The performative grief embedded in metaphors like the “widowed city” reflects collective trauma.🕯 Widow, 🏚 Desolate city, 💔 Weeping woman🔁 Illustrates metaphorical shifts from triumph to lament in intertextual theology (© Labahn in Holt 2003, p. 5).
The Book of IsaiahHolt’s stress on semantic space shows that metaphors like “light to the nations” should not be literalized. They open a range of ethical, eschatological, and political meanings in Jewish identity and mission.🌟 Light, 🌿 Root, 🏞 Mountain🌀 Metaphors create open, theological meaning—not fixed doctrinal claims (© Holt 2003, p. 4).
🧪 William Blake’s “The Marriage of Heaven and Hell”Blake’s prophetic-poetic language, full of paradoxical metaphors, can be re-read via Holt’s approach as theological performance. His metaphorical inversions (e.g., Hell as energy) perform ideological critique of institutional religion.🔥 Hell as energy, 👼 Angel as passive, ⚡ Proverbs of Hell🧠 Metaphors function ideologically, challenging dominant religious discourse (© Nielsen in Holt 2003, p. 5).
Criticism Against “Metaphor in Prophetic Literature” by Else K. Holt

⚖️ Overemphasis on Metaphor as Theological Necessity

  • While Holt argues that metaphor is indispensable for speaking of the divine, critics may contend that this approach risks marginalizing other literary and rhetorical tools (e.g., narrative, irony, structure) which also convey complex theological ideas.

🔄 Limited Engagement with Broader Literary Theory

  • The article engages metaphor within the biblical studies context, but it does not deeply interact with secular or modern metaphor theories (e.g., Lakoff & Johnson’s Conceptual Metaphor Theory), potentially narrowing its cross-disciplinary applicability.

🚪 Exclusion of Non-Theological Readings

  • Holt’s focus is primarily theological and exegetical; literary critics might argue that this emphasis overlooks political, feminist, or postcolonial readings of prophetic metaphor that could yield alternative insights.

🧱 Assumption of Metaphorical Primacy

  • The claim that metaphor is the dominant or most important linguistic mode in prophetic literature could be challenged by scholars who view historical context, poetics, or redaction history as equally crucial.

🔍 Insufficient Critical Distance from Source Texts

  • Some may criticize the article for adopting a reverential tone toward the biblical text, lacking the critical distance that literary theory or cultural criticism often demand when analyzing religious literature.

🧠 Ambiguity in Defining Metaphor’s Performative Role

  • Though the article introduces the concept of “performative metaphor,” it does not fully theorize what that entails in literary terms, leaving the function and scope of this role somewhat vague.

🌍 Western-Centric Perspective

  • Holt’s framework is rooted in Nordic and Western biblical scholarship. Critics from global or comparative religious traditions might argue that it doesn’t account for how metaphor operates differently in non-Western prophetic or sacred traditions.
Representative Quotations from “Metaphor in Prophetic Literature” by Else K. Holt with Explanation
📜 Quotation💡 Explanation📌 Thematic Focus
“When we talk about God, the absolute otherness, we have to talk tentatively, that is: in metaphor.” (© Holt 2003, p. 3)Holt emphasizes that metaphor is not decorative but essential for theological language, especially in portraying a transcendent God.🕊️ Theological Function of Metaphor
“Exegetes… have translated this imagery into plain language… the texts have been demythologised.” (© Holt 2003, p. 4)This critique targets reductionism in historical-critical methods, which strip texts of poetic and symbolic richness by overly rational interpretations.⚠️ Critique of Literalism
“Metaphors are not as harmless as they may seem… metaphors are often weapons in ideological wars.” (© Nielsen in Holt 2003, p. 5)Quoting Kirsten Nielsen, Holt points out that metaphors carry ideological weight and must be handled with critical awareness.⚔️ Ideological Critique
“Texts are not islands, but are parts in intertextual networks… metaphors function as markers in such networks.” (© Nielsen in Holt 2003, p. 5)Metaphors link biblical texts across time and themes, functioning as intertextual clues that reflect evolving theology and literary form.🔗 Intertextuality
“A metaphor… creates a sense of meaning… between the text and its reader.” (© Labahn in Holt 2003, p. 5)Labahn’s insight, cited by Holt, supports a reader-response view where metaphor is activated in the interpretive space of reader and text.👁️ Reader-Response Theory
“Israel, who was once a flock of dispersed and devoured sheep, is restored to its initial pasture-land by God, its shepherd…” (© van Hecke in Holt 2003, p. 6)This pastoral metaphor illustrates narrative transformation, showing how metaphor enables shifts in roles and meanings within prophetic texts.🐑 Metaphorical Transformation
“Both doom and hope dispossess and repossess rights to the myth of YHWH and Israel.” (© Diamond in Holt 2003, p. 6)Diamond reflects on the rhetorical interplay of destructive and restorative metaphors in Jeremiah, revealing theological ambiguity.⚖️ Rhetorical Tension
“Metaphor will remain in the centre of our exegetical attention.” (© van Hecke in Holt 2003, p. 6)A concluding affirmation that metaphor should not be a side topic, but central to serious biblical and literary analysis.🎯 Methodological Imperative
Suggested Readings: “Metaphor in Prophetic Literature” by Else K. Holt
  1. Kratz, R. G. “The Prophetic Literature.” The Hebrew Bible: A Critical Companion, edited by John Barton, Princeton University Press, 2016, pp. 133–59. JSTOR, https://doi.org/10.2307/j.ctv7h0snt.10. Accessed 12 May 2025.
  2. Ryken, Leland. “METAPHOR IN THE PSALMS.” Christianity and Literature, vol. 31, no. 3, 1982, pp. 9–29. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/44311013. Accessed 12 May 2025.
  3. White, Hugh C. “Metaphor and Myth: Percy, Ricoeur and Frye.” A Wise and Discerning Mind: Essays in Honor of Burke O. Long, edited by Saul M. Olyan and Robert C. Culley, Brown Judaic Studies, 2020, pp. 245–70. JSTOR, https://doi.org/10.2307/j.ctvzgb93t.24. Accessed 12 May 2025.
  4. Sherman, Tina M. “Other Plant Metaphors.” Plant Metaphors in Prophetic Condemnations of Israel and Judah, The Society of Biblical Literature, 2023, pp. 223–60. JSTOR, https://doi.org/10.2307/jj.8784669.13. Accessed 12 May 2025.

“Metaphor As Hermeneutic” by Richard D. Johnson Sheehan: Summary and Critique

“Metaphor As Hermeneutic” by Richard D. Johnson Sheehan first appeared in 1999 in Rhetoric Society Quarterly (Vol. 29, No. 2, pp. 47–64).

"Metaphor As Hermeneutic" by Richard D. Johnson Sheehan: Summary and Critique
Introduction: “Metaphor As Hermeneutic” by Richard D. Johnson Sheehan

“Metaphor As Hermeneutic” by Richard D. Johnson Sheehan first appeared in 1999 in Rhetoric Society Quarterly (Vol. 29, No. 2, pp. 47–64). In this influential essay, Sheehan challenges traditional semantic and cognitive theories of metaphor by proposing a rhetorical-hermeneutic perspective that focuses on how metaphors are used rather than how they work. Drawing from thinkers like Donald Davidson, Hans-Georg Gadamer, and I.A. Richards, Sheehan argues that metaphors serve not primarily to transfer meaning but to invite the invention of narratives through interpretation. Instead of treating metaphor as a deviation from literal language or as a cognitive interaction between schemas, Sheehan situates metaphor within the interpreter’s active, context-bound process of understanding, emphasizing stages of identification, invention, and narration. His work is significant in literary theory because it shifts attention from the internal mechanics of language to the social, interpretive acts that shape meaning, aligning metaphorical understanding closely with hermeneutic traditions. This reconceptualization not only redefines metaphor’s role in rhetoric and literature but also aligns with broader movements toward rhetorical and pragmatic views of language in late twentieth-century literary studies.

Summary of “Metaphor As Hermeneutic” by Richard D. Johnson Sheehan

🎨 Metaphor as a Tool for Inventing Narratives

“Metaphors serve as a basis for inventing narratives” (Sheehan, 1999, p. 47).
Rather than viewing metaphors as mysterious cognitive mechanisms, Sheehan emphasizes that metaphors help create new ways of understanding and interpreting reality through narrative construction.


🌟 The Shift from How Metaphors Work to How They Are Used

“The purpose of this essay, therefore, is to discuss how we use metaphors” (Sheehan, 1999, p. 48).
Sheehan critiques the traditional semantic and cognitive approaches, insisting that metaphor theory should focus on use (rhetorical-pragmatic) instead of mechanism (semantic-linguistic).


🔥 Meaning Lies with the Interpreter, Not the Text

“The meaning of Abbey’s metaphor is dependent completely on the interpreter’s prior experiences and beliefs” (Sheehan, 1999, p. 48).
Sheehan argues that metaphoric meaning is generated not by the author or phrase itself but by the reader’s own interpretive framework and experiential background.


🎯 Metaphor as a Device for Perspective Shifting

“A metaphor is a rhetorical device for altering one’s perspective” (Sheehan, 1999, p. 49).
Following thinkers like Burke and Rorty, Sheehan underlines how metaphors encourage audiences to reconceptualize phenomena from fresh angles, effectively changing how we experience the world.


🧩 Critique of Orthodox Theories (Interaction and Substitution Models)

“The debate over metaphor has been almost exclusively over ‘how metaphors work'” (Sheehan, 1999, p. 52).
Sheehan critiques both neo-Aristotelian and interactionist models, claiming they erroneously assume metaphors work differently than literal expressions.


🛠️ Davidson and Searle: Metaphor Belongs to Use, Not Meaning

“Metaphor belongs exclusively to the domain of use” (Sheehan quoting Davidson, 1999, p. 53).
Drawing on Davidson and Searle, Sheehan highlights that metaphors do not possess hidden meanings but function by creatively prompting new interpretations within normal linguistic usage.


🔄 Hermeneutic Circle in Interpreting Metaphors

“Understanding is always an invention of the interpreter” (Sheehan, 1999, p. 56).
Using Gadamer and Heidegger’s hermeneutic circle, Sheehan argues that interpreting a metaphor involves a dynamic, ongoing negotiation between the interpreter’s expectations and the evolving context.


🧠 Identification, Invention, and Narration: The Process of Metaphor Interpretation

“All three of these stages—identification, invention, and narration—are part of a broader hermeneutic act” (Sheehan, 1999, p. 57).
Sheehan introduces a three-stage model of metaphor use: first, recognizing the metaphor; second, inventing its meaning; and third, integrating it into a broader narrative.


📚 Metaphors as Foundations for Scientific and Cultural Narratives

“The whole works of scientific research… are hardly more than the patient repetition… of a fertile metaphor” (Burke quoted in Sheehan, 1999, p. 60).
He shows how metaphors like “nature is a machine” have historically shaped major scientific paradigms and cultural understandings.


🌀 Conclusion: Metaphors as Pragmatic Instruments

“A metaphor is a tool that can be used to guide or change perspective” (Sheehan, 1999, p. 64).
Ultimately, metaphors are valuable not for their semantic properties but for their rhetorical power to transform perception and meaning-making.


Theoretical Terms/Concepts in “Metaphor As Hermeneutic” by Richard D. Johnson Sheehan
🌟 Term/Concept📚 Explanation🖋️ Usage in the Article
🎨 Metaphor as HermeneuticMetaphor is a tool for interpretation, not a linguistic puzzle to solve.Sheehan shifts focus from how metaphors work to how they are used to construct meaning through narratives (Sheehan, 1999, p. 47).
🔄 Hermeneutic CircleInterpretation involves a continuous dialogue between the part and the whole in understanding.Sheehan applies Gadamer’s hermeneutic circle to show how interpreters mediate between prior expectations, expression, and context (p. 56).
🛠️ Domain of UseMetaphors function within the pragmatic use of language, not by special cognitive effects.Following Davidson, Sheehan argues metaphors “belong exclusively to the domain of use” rather than containing hidden meanings (p. 53).
🧠 Interpretive InventionMeaning is invented by interpreters based on prior experience and narrative context.He shows that readers invent meanings for metaphors depending on their background, not extracting pre-encoded ideas (p. 48, p. 58).
🎯 Perspective ShiftMetaphors reshape how we perceive and talk about reality by inviting different viewpoints.Sheehan cites Burke and Rorty to argue that metaphors alter perspectives rather than merely decorate speech (p. 49).
🧩 Identification (Stage 1)Recognizing a statement as metaphorical when it contrasts with prior knowledge/context.In the John example, the hearer identifies “John is a priest” as metaphorical because it contradicts what she knows (p. 57–58).
🛤️ Invention (Stage 2)Creating a coherent meaning by aligning the metaphor with the surrounding narrative.After identification, interpreters invent a meaning to fit the metaphor within their narrative framework (p. 58–59).
📖 Narration (Stage 3)Expanding and integrating the metaphor into broader narratives and cultural understandings.Metaphors are used to build extended narratives, like “nature as machine” shaping scientific paradigms (p. 60–61).
🧬 Meta-narrativesDeep-seated cultural stories constructed through long-term metaphorical invention.Sheehan explains how dormant metaphors like “time is money” have become part of Western cultural meta-narratives (p. 62–63).
🔥 Critique of SemanticismCriticism of the idea that metaphors function differently from literal language due to semantics.Sheehan critiques traditional metaphor theories for their faith in semantic or cognitive causality, calling it unnecessary and misleading (p. 52–54).
Contribution of “Metaphor As Hermeneutic” by Richard D. Johnson Sheehan to Literary Theory/Theories

📜 1. Contribution to Hermeneutics

  • Contribution: Sheehan expands hermeneutic theory by positioning metaphor interpretation as an inventive act rather than a semantic decoding process.
  • Reference: “The interpreter’s understanding of a metaphor is dependent completely on his or her inventions of meaning within a contextual narrative” (Sheehan, 1999, p. 55).
  • Impact: Connects metaphor theory with Gadamerian hermeneutics, emphasizing interpretation as situated, evolving, and contextual rather than uncovering objective meaning.

🔄 2. Contribution to Rhetorical Theory

  • Contribution: Reorients metaphor studies within rhetoric, focusing on how metaphors are used persuasively rather than on internal cognitive mechanisms.
  • Reference: “If rhetoric is primarily about how words are used to achieve particular ends, then a rhetorical view of metaphor should concern how people use them, not how they work” (Sheehan, 1999, p. 48).
  • Impact: Revives classical rhetorical concerns (use, persuasion, audience impact) over formalist concerns (structure, internal relations).

🔍 3. Contribution to Deconstruction/Poststructuralism

  • Contribution: Challenges the literal/figurative binary by arguing that metaphors are not ontologically different from literal statements.
  • Reference: “Metaphors gain meaning much like other parts of natural language” (Sheehan, 1999, p. 54).
  • Impact: Aligns with Derrida’s poststructuralist critique that meaning is always deferred and that distinctions between “literal” and “figurative” are unstable.

📖 4. Contribution to Narrative Theory

  • Contribution: Frames metaphors as foundational for inventing narratives that structure human experience.
  • Reference: “Metaphors serve as a basis for inventing narratives” (Sheehan, 1999, p. 47).
  • Impact: Supports narratological approaches by showing how metaphorical language generates evolving story-worlds and frameworks of meaning.

🧠 5. Contribution to Cognitive Linguistics (Critical)

  • Contribution: Critiques and complicates cognitive theories (e.g., Lakoff and Johnson) by emphasizing the situated, contextual invention over universal cognitive mechanisms.
  • Reference: “Metaphor runs the same linguistic tracks that the plainest sentences do” (Sheehan quoting Davidson, 1999, p. 64).
  • Impact: Shifts attention from hardwired cognition to interpretive negotiation, aligning metaphor use with rhetorical and social practices rather than universal cognitive operations.

🎯 6. Contribution to Phenomenology

  • Contribution: Emphasizes the lived experience of interpreting metaphors, grounded in personal, situated horizons of meaning.
  • Reference: “The interpreter negotiates among her prejudices, the words of the text/speaker, and the overall contextual narrative” (Sheehan, 1999, p. 57).
  • Impact: Resonates with phenomenological hermeneutics (e.g., Heidegger and Gadamer) where meaning arises from existential engagement with the text.

🖋️ 7. Contribution to Interpretation Theory

  • Contribution: Redefines interpretation as a creative act rather than a discovery of pre-existing meanings.
  • Reference: “Meaning is wholly dependent on its use to invent a meaning that coheres with the interpreter’s contextual narrative” (Sheehan, 1999, p. 60).
  • Impact: Supports interpretive pluralism — multiple valid readings depending on varied contexts and backgrounds.

🔥 8. Contribution to Pragmatics

  • Contribution: Locates metaphor meaning in social-pragmatic usage rather than internal textual properties.
  • Reference: “Metaphor is something brought off by the imaginative employment of words and sentences” (Sheehan quoting Davidson, 1999, p. 53).
  • Impact: Backs pragmatic literary theories emphasizing meaning as an effect of communicative action in specific situations.

🌍 9. Contribution to Cultural Studies

  • Contribution: Shows how metaphors evolve into cultural meta-narratives that shape collective experience and ideology.
  • Reference: “Dead metaphors like ‘time is money’ have become cultural themes woven into Western narratives” (Sheehan, 1999, p. 62).
  • Impact: Demonstrates that culture itself is constituted by sedimented metaphors, aligning metaphor theory with cultural semiotics.

Examples of Critiques Through “Metaphor As Hermeneutic” by Richard D. Johnson Sheehan
🎨📚 Work🖋️ Critique through Metaphor as Hermeneutic🎯 Explanation
🌵“The Road” by Cormac McCarthyThe barren, ash-covered landscape as a “dead sea” invites inventing a narrative of isolation and survival.Readers’ interpretations rely on personal concepts of desolation and hope, crafting meaning from the novel’s metaphoric world. (Sheehan, p. 55–57)
🌊“Moby-Dick” by Herman MelvilleThe White Whale metaphorically functions as a projection of obsession and unknowable truth.Rather than “decoding” Moby-Dick, readers invent narratives based on prior beliefs about fate, struggle, and nature. (Sheehan, p. 48, 60)
🔥“The Waste Land” by T.S. EliotEliot’s image of the barren wasteland invites endless invention of modern alienation and spiritual drought.Meaning emerges hermeneutically through the reader’s negotiation of fragmented imagery, not through “hidden” semantic content. (Sheehan, p. 55–58)
🕊️“Beloved” by Toni MorrisonThe character Beloved as a living ghost metaphor urges reinterpretations of memory, trauma, and identity.Metaphor serves to invent shifting narratives about slavery’s haunting legacy, shaped by each reader’s cultural and historical lens. (Sheehan, p. 59–61)
Criticism Against “Metaphor As Hermeneutic” by Richard D. Johnson Sheehan

1. Overemphasis on Reader Subjectivity

  • Critics argue that Sheehan’s insistence on the interpreter’s invention of meaning risks radical relativism, where any interpretation could be justified without constraint.
  • Concern: Without any anchor, interpretations could become untethered from textual evidence or authorial intent.

🧩 2. Neglect of Cognitive Dimensions of Metaphor

  • Cognitive linguists (like Lakoff and Johnson) might object that Sheehan underestimates the deep cognitive structures that make metaphors meaningful across cultures.
  • Concern: Metaphor is not purely invented situationally; it also taps into shared conceptual systems.

📚 3. Undermining the Literary Craft of Metaphor

  • By treating metaphors as mere tools for narrative invention, Sheehan risks flattening the artistry and specific craft of how metaphors are constructed by writers.
  • Concern: Authors’ deliberate choices and stylistic innovations may be overlooked in favor of focusing only on reader response.

🧠 4. Insufficient Engagement with Historical Contexts

  • Critics from New Historicism or Cultural Studies could argue that Sheehan’s model ignores the socio-political contexts in which metaphors are created and interpreted.
  • Concern: Meaning isn’t invented solely by individuals but is deeply shaped by power structures, ideologies, and history.

🔍 5. Reduction of Metaphor’s Epistemological Power

  • Philosophical critics could argue that Sheehan downplays metaphors’ ability to reveal new aspects of reality, reducing them to narrative tricks.
  • Concern: Metaphor isn’t just about “inventing” stories; it can also disclose truths not otherwise articulable in literal language.

6. Ambiguity in Distinguishing ‘Literal’ and ‘Metaphorical’ Use

  • Although Sheehan critiques the literal/figurative divide, he doesn’t provide a clear methodology for distinguishing when a metaphor is being used metaphorically or literally.
  • Concern: Readers may be left without guidance on how to responsibly identify and interpret metaphors.

🚪 7. Closure Against Scientific and Linguistic Advances

  • By largely rejecting semantic/cognitive models, Sheehan could be seen as closing the door to useful insights from neuroscience, psychology, and computational linguistics about metaphor.
  • Concern: A hermeneutic-only view might isolate literary theory from interdisciplinary developments.

Representative Quotations from “Metaphor As Hermeneutic” by Richard D. Johnson Sheehan with Explanation
🌟 Quotation🧠 Explanation
🏔️ “The meaning of Abbey’s metaphor is dependent completely on the interpreter’s prior experiences and beliefs.” (p. 48)Meaning isn’t inherent in the metaphor itself; it is created by readers’ personal histories and worldviews.
🔄 “Metaphors should be defined by how they are used, not how they work.” (p. 48)Sheehan shifts the focus from cognitive mechanics to practical application—emphasizing use over mechanism.
🎻 “Just as studying the physics of a violin rarely makes someone a better musician, knowing how metaphors work rarely makes one a better writer or speaker.” (p. 48)Knowing technical aspects of metaphor doesn’t necessarily help in using them effectively for communication.
🔥 “Our pretense to do without metaphor is never more than a bluff waiting to be called.” (citing Richards, p. 50)Metaphors are fundamental to all human language and thought—inescapable and ever-present.
🕰️ “Western culture layers metaphors like ‘time is a stream’ and ‘time is money’ that cannot be merged into a single narrative.” (p. 49)Different metaphors create competing, irreconcilable worldviews rather than unifying perspectives.
🧩 “Both sides of metaphor theory assume metaphors ’cause’ something in the mind of a passive reader.” (p. 52)Sheehan criticizes the assumption that metaphors are automatic triggers in cognition instead of collaborative acts.
🗣️ “All communication by speech assumes the interplay of inventive construction and inventive construal.” (citing Davidson, p. 53)Meaning-making is active and dynamic, not a passive reception—even outside metaphors.
🎭 “Metaphors are used to urge us toward further and further invention of meaning.” (p. 54)Rather than “delivering” meaning, metaphors inspire continuous creative interpretation.
🔄 “An interpreter’s understanding of a metaphor is dependent completely on her inventions of meaning within a contextual narrative.” (p. 55)Interpretation is context-sensitive and dynamic, not universal or fixed.
🛠️ “A metaphor is a tool that can be used to guide or change perspective.” (p. 64)Metaphors function as tools for transformation, not static ornaments or decorations in language.
Suggested Readings: “Metaphor As Hermeneutic” by Richard D. Johnson Sheehan
  1. Richard D. Johnson Sheehan. “Metaphor as Hermeneutic.” Rhetoric Society Quarterly, vol. 29, no. 2, 1999, pp. 47–64. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/3886085. Accessed 26 Apr. 2025.
  2. Grant, A. J. “Vico and Bultmann on Myth: The Problem with Demythologizing.” Rhetoric Society Quarterly, vol. 30, no. 4, 2000, pp. 49–82. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/3886117. Accessed 26 Apr. 2025.
  3. Sobolev, Dennis. “Metaphor Revisited.” New Literary History, vol. 39, no. 4, 2008, pp. 903–29. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/20533122. Accessed 26 Apr. 2025.
  4. Steen, Gerard J. “Identifying Metaphor in Language: A Cognitive Approach.” Style, vol. 36, no. 3, 2002, pp. 386–406. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.5325/style.36.3.386. Accessed 26 Apr. 2025.

“Metaphor as Argument: Rhetorical and Epistemic Advantages of Extended Metaphors” by Steve Oswald and Alain Rihs: Summary and Critique

“Metaphor as Argument: Rhetorical and Epistemic Advantages of Extended Metaphors” by Steve Oswald and Alain Rihs first appeared in Argumentation (Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht) in 2013.

"Metaphor as Argument: Rhetorical and Epistemic Advantages of Extended Metaphors" by Steve Oswald and Alain Rihs: Summary and Critique
Introduction: “Metaphor as Argument: Rhetorical and Epistemic Advantages of Extended Metaphors” by Steve Oswald and Alain Rihs

“Metaphor as Argument: Rhetorical and Epistemic Advantages of Extended Metaphors” by Steve Oswald and Alain Rihs first appeared in Argumentation (Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht) in 2013. The article investigates how extended metaphors, particularly in political discourse, function not merely as stylistic embellishments but as powerful argumentative tools with significant rhetorical and epistemic advantages. Oswald and Rihs argue that extended metaphors can self-legitimize through repeated instantiations of metaphorical mappings, effectively leading audiences to accept metaphorical content as literal truth. Moreover, the recognition of an extended metaphor’s sophistication enhances the speaker’s ethos, boosting their perceived competence and trustworthiness. Grounded in cognitive theories like Relevance Theory and epistemic vigilance, the study shows that extended metaphors can fulfill cognitive expectations for coherence and justification, ultimately stabilizing beliefs. In literary theory and discourse analysis, their work is vital because it bridges rhetorical strategies and cognitive processing, revealing how deeply metaphor shapes not just understanding but belief formation and political persuasion.

Summary of “Metaphor as Argument: Rhetorical and Epistemic Advantages of Extended Metaphors” by Steve Oswald and Alain Rihs

🔵 Extended metaphors serve as self-reinforcing arguments.

“Each instantiation of the metaphorical mapping in the text may function as a confirmation of the overall relevance of the main core mapping.” (Oswald & Rihs, 2013)
💬 Comment: Each new use of the metaphor strengthens the main idea, making it seem increasingly true through repetition and coherence.

🟢 Extended metaphors build the speaker’s credibility (ethos).

“The recognition of an extended metaphor’s sophistication and relevance […] can benefit the speaker’s perceived competence.” (Oswald & Rihs, 2013)
💬 Comment: If the metaphor appears clever and fits well, it reflects positively on the speaker’s intelligence and trustworthiness.

🟣 Extended metaphors help satisfy epistemic vigilance filters.

“Extended metaphors may fulfil the requirements of epistemic vigilance and lead to the stabilisation of a belief.” (Oswald & Rihs, 2013)
💬 Comment: Because they seem internally consistent and well-supported, they pass the audience’s mental checks for truthfulness and reliability.

🔴 Comprehension leads to belief in metaphorical communication.

“We will focus on the relationship between understanding and believing and accordingly try to highlight the importance of comprehension with respect to beliefs.” (Oswald & Rihs, 2013)
💬 Comment: The more a metaphor is understood, the more likely it is to be accepted as representing reality.

🟠 Extended metaphors can blur into literal beliefs.

“The metaphor may cease to be perceived as one, turning what was at first metaphorically construed into a representation about an actual state of affairs one can believe to be true.” (Oswald & Rihs, 2013)
💬 Comment: Over time, the audience may forget it was a metaphor and treat the metaphorical idea as literal truth.

🟡 Despite higher processing costs, they provide rhetorical rewards.

“Extended metaphors are demanding in terms of effort […] but their cognitive cost has to be offset by some sort of benefit.” (Oswald & Rihs, 2013)
💬 Comment: Although complex metaphors are mentally taxing, they are justified if they yield strong persuasive or epistemic effects.

🔵 Coherence across instances builds stronger arguments.

“The various occurrences of an extended metaphor in a text can be argumentatively used so as to function as a set of justifications for the metaphor.” (Oswald & Rihs, 2013)
💬 Comment: When a metaphor is consistently woven through discourse, each use reinforces and justifies the overall narrative.

🟢 Extended metaphors imitate analogical argument structures.

“The more you instantiate your target domain in terms of your source domain in an argument, the stronger the argument.” (Oswald & Rihs, 2013)
💬 Comment: Like analogies, metaphors gain strength when their logic is applied consistently and across multiple examples.

🟣 Plausible repeated mappings boost metaphor relevance.

“The more plausible the metaphorical mappings exploited in an extended metaphor are […] the more its overall perceived relevance increases.” (Oswald & Rihs, 2013)
💬 Comment: Logical, believable connections between metaphor and reality make the audience more likely to accept the metaphor as fitting.

🔴 Extended metaphors can activate confirmation bias.

“Extended metaphor could be thought to cognitively function as an argument meant to ‘de-metaphorise’ the metaphor.” (Oswald & Rihs, 2013)
💬 Comment: As more evidence is presented, audiences may favor information that supports the metaphor, reinforcing belief without skepticism.

Theoretical Terms/Concepts in “Metaphor as Argument: Rhetorical and Epistemic Advantages of Extended Metaphors” by Steve Oswald and Alain Rihs
📌 Term/Concept📖 Explanation🛠️ Usage in the Article
🔥 Extended MetaphorA metaphor elaborated across multiple parts of a discourse, connecting many elements of the source and target domains.Seen as a powerful argumentative device to stabilize beliefs and even shift metaphorical constructs into literal interpretations.
🧠 Epistemic VigilanceCognitive mechanisms humans use to evaluate the trustworthiness and truthfulness of communicated information.Authors argue extended metaphors can satisfy epistemic vigilance by appearing coherent and plausible, enhancing acceptance of beliefs.
🛤️ Conceptual MappingSystematic correspondences between elements of two conceptual domains (source and target).Repeated mappings in extended metaphors are used to gradually reinforce and validate the metaphorical construal.
🗣️ EthosRhetorical appeal based on the speaker’s credibility, expertise, or character.Building a sophisticated metaphor boosts the speaker’s perceived competence and trustworthiness.
🧩 Ad hoc Concept FormationCognitive process of adjusting or extending a word’s meaning dynamically during communication for relevance.Used to explain how metaphors are processed — literal meanings are widened or adapted to context.
Confirmation BiasTendency to favor information that confirms existing beliefs or assumptions.Authors suggest that the repeated affirmations within an extended metaphor trigger confirmation bias, reinforcing belief in the metaphor.
🌐 Relevance Theory (RT)A theory explaining that communication aims at achieving the most relevant cognitive effects with the least processing effort.Used as a cognitive basis for why and how extended metaphors are persuasive despite their complexity.
🧵 CoherenceLogical and meaningful connectivity among different parts of a discourse.The multiple instances of the extended metaphor create coherence, helping build a cumulative argument.
⚖️ Argument by ExampleA type of argument where specific instances are used to support a general conclusion.Each instantiation of the metaphor (e.g., USA’s military actions) acts as an example reinforcing the USA=Empire mapping.
🎭 De-metaphorisationThe process by which a metaphor shifts toward being perceived as literal truth.Extended metaphors can gradually turn a figurative depiction into a literal belief (e.g., “USA is an empire” becoming a perceived fact).
Contribution of “Metaphor as Argument: Rhetorical and Epistemic Advantages of Extended Metaphors” by Steve Oswald and Alain Rihs to Literary Theory/Theories

🔵 🎯 Cognitive Poetics and Cognitive Literary Theory

  • 📖 The article links metaphor processing to cognitive effort and epistemic effects, directly contributing to cognitive approaches in literary theory.
  • 🗨️ “We will consider possible perlocutionary effects of metaphoric creativity, in particular as to what regards belief fixation…” (Oswald & Rihs, 2013, p. 22)
  • 👉 Shows how literary metaphors aren’t only decorative but also cognitively shape understanding and belief systems.

🟣 🎯 Rhetorical Theory (Neo-Aristotelian Rhetoric)

  • 📖 The paper revives Aristotle’s notions of ethos, pathos, and logos, especially showing how extended metaphors enhance speaker ethos.
  • 🗨️ “Well-thought extended metaphors… can positively influence the speaker’s perceived image.” (Oswald & Rihs, 2013, p. 37)
  • 👉 This connects metaphor to rhetorical persuasion, enriching the study of persuasive strategies in literary and political discourse.

🟠 🎯 Structuralism (through Conceptual Mapping)

  • 📖 Their use of conceptual domains and mappings fits structuralist models where meaning emerges from systematic correspondences between structures.
  • 🗨️ “The metaphor maps systematically establishes correspondences between representations…” (Oswald & Rihs, 2013, p. 5)
  • 👉 Strengthens the idea that meaning in literature is relational, structured through recurring metaphorical patterns.

🟡 🎯 Relevance Theory in Literary Pragmatics

  • 📖 By applying Relevance Theory to literary metaphors, they bridge pragmatics with literary studies.
  • 🗨️ “Relevance is therefore defined here in terms of balance between processing effort and cognitive effect.” (Oswald & Rihs, 2013, p. 12)
  • 👉 This encourages a pragmatic lens for studying how metaphors achieve literary impact based on cognitive processing.

🟢 🎯 Critical Discourse Analysis (CDA)

  • 📖 Their analysis of metaphor as a political tool (e.g., USA as Empire) aligns with CDA’s interest in how language shapes ideology.
  • 🗨️ “The extended metaphor functions as an argumentative device geared towards the validation of epistemic claims.” (Oswald & Rihs, 2013, p. 32)
  • 👉 Suggests that literary metaphors are political instruments, influencing public belief, not merely aesthetic flourishes.

🔴 🎯 Post-Structuralism (De-metaphorisation Process)

  • 📖 The fading of metaphor into literal belief connects to post-structuralist ideas about the instability and transformation of meanings.
  • 🗨️ “Extended metaphors may lead their addressee to eventually abandon the metaphorical construal altogether…” (Oswald & Rihs, 2013, p. 24)
  • 👉 Emphasizes how literary language undermines or redefines stable categories over time.

🎯 Argumentation Theory in Literature

  • 📖 Positions metaphors not just as stylistic devices but as arguments that structure reader belief, linking to Toulmin’s model and Perelman’s New Rhetoric.
  • 🗨️ “Extended metaphors are ideally suited to contribute material that can be used for argumentative purposes.” (Oswald & Rihs, 2013, p. 18)
  • 👉 Enhances literary theory by showing how narratives subtly argue, not just narrate.

🌟 Summary:

Steve Oswald and Alain Rihs offer a multi-theoretical impact — their work helps literary theory shift toward seeing metaphors as cognitive, rhetorical, discursive, ideological, and argumentative forces, not mere aesthetic ornaments.

Examples of Critiques Through “Metaphor as Argument: Rhetorical and Epistemic Advantages of Extended Metaphors” by Steve Oswald and Alain Rihs
🌟 Literary Work✍️ Critique through Extended Metaphor Argumentation📖 Example from the Work🧠 Link to Oswald & Rihs
🐳 Moby-Dick (Herman Melville)Melville uses the extended metaphor of the whale as a symbol for fate, evil, and the unknowable, which slowly transforms into a literal force that Ahab fights.“The whale was no longer a whale; it was the embodiment of all evil.”Like Oswald & Rihs suggest, the extended metaphor de-metaphorizes, leading readers to believe in the whale as an actual malevolent force.
🍎 Paradise Lost (John Milton)Milton’s depiction of Satan as a heroic rebel uses an extended metaphor of Satan as a political revolutionary, gradually convincing readers emotionally and cognitively.“Better to reign in Hell, than serve in Heaven.”As in Oswald & Rihs’ analysis, the extended metaphor enhances ethos (Satan’s perceived dignity), subtly urging belief in his cause.
👒 The Great Gatsby (F. Scott Fitzgerald)Fitzgerald’s use of the green light as an extended metaphor for hope and the American Dream evolves until it seems almost a real, driving force behind Gatsby’s tragedy.“He stretched out his arms toward the dark water in a curious way… and distinguished nothing except a single green light.”Following Oswald & Rihs, the constant recurrence of the metaphor self-validates the green light as real, making readers emotionally accept it as Gatsby’s destiny.
🦅 Heart of Darkness (Joseph Conrad)The “darkness” operates as an extended metaphor for colonial evil, slowly literalizing horror until it becomes undeniable, not symbolic.“The horror! The horror!”Per Oswald & Rihs, extended metaphor turns abstraction into apparent truth, fulfilling the epistemic vigilance by linking experiences to believable evil.
Criticism Against “Metaphor as Argument: Rhetorical and Epistemic Advantages of Extended Metaphors” by Steve Oswald and Alain Rihs
  • 🔵 Overemphasis on Cognitive Reception:
    The article heavily stresses cognitive processing and belief fixation but downplays emotional and aesthetic responses that also influence metaphor interpretation (especially in literature and poetry).
  • 🟢 Potential Oversimplification of Audience Reactions:
    It assumes audiences will process extended metaphors uniformly toward belief acceptance, but real-world audiences may resist, reinterpret, or reject metaphors based on ideology, culture, or context.
  • 🟡 Neglect of Multimodal Metaphors:
    The focus is mostly on verbal/metaphorical mappings in text, ignoring that modern political or literary discourse often uses images, sounds, and gestures that extend metaphors non-verbally.
  • 🟠 Possible Confusion Between ‘Literalization’ and ‘Manipulation’:
    While they argue that metaphors can “de-metaphorize,” critics might say that this borders on manipulation, blurring the ethical lines between convincing and deceiving audiences.
  • 🔴 Insufficient Treatment of Failed Extended Metaphors:
    The paper does not adequately discuss cases where extended metaphors collapse or backfire, leading to skepticism rather than belief.
  • 🟣 Reliance on Relevance Theory Alone:
    Their analysis heavily depends on Relevance Theory (Sperber & Wilson), which, while powerful, is not the only cognitive framework for understanding language and metaphor (e.g., Conceptual Metaphor Theory, Frame Semantics).
  • 🟤 Limited Empirical Validation:
    Their claims are mainly theoretical and based on close reading; critics might argue that experimental or empirical data (e.g., surveys, comprehension tests) would strengthen or challenge their conclusions.
  • Possible Bias in Example Selection:
    Using extreme political examples (like Hitler or aggressive nationalism) risks biasing the conclusions about how metaphors operate in less extreme or neutral discourses.
Representative Quotations from “Metaphor as Argument: Rhetorical and Epistemic Advantages of Extended Metaphors” by Steve Oswald and Alain Rihs with Explanation
QuotationExplanation
🌟“Extended metaphors carry self-validating claims that increase the chances of their content being accepted.”➔ Extended metaphors reinforce themselves through repetition, making the audience more likely to accept them as truth.
🧠“Extended metaphors may fulfil the requirements of epistemic vigilance and lead to the stabilisation of a belief.”➔ Extended metaphors can bypass our cognitive defenses by appearing coherent and credible, solidifying beliefs.
“Recurring exploitations of a metaphor can converge towards the justification of the proposed metaphorical construal.”➔ Repeated metaphor usage incrementally convinces readers that the metaphor reflects reality.
🔥“Extended metaphors may lead their addressee to eventually abandon the metaphorical construal altogether.”➔ Through accumulation of examples, audiences may stop seeing the metaphor as figurative and take it literally.
💬“Processing metaphors is governed by a principle of relevance: cognitive cost must be offset by benefit.”➔ Audience mental effort in interpreting extended metaphors is rewarded by perceived deeper understanding or truth.
🧩“Each instantiation of the metaphorical mapping in the text may function as a confirmation of the overall relevance.”➔ Every metaphorical example acts like a puzzle piece confirming the big picture suggested by the metaphor.
📜“The discursive nature of extended metaphors makes them approachable with discourse-analytical tools.”➔ Because they stretch across a whole text, extended metaphors are open to systematic analysis like arguments are.
🚀“Extended metaphors involve complex multi-stage representational operations triggered cumulatively as discourse unfolds.”➔ Audiences must continually interpret and update the metaphor throughout the discourse, enhancing its persuasive power.
🛡️“Extended metaphors can positively influence speaker ethos if their sophistication is recognised by the hearer.”➔ The more sophisticated the metaphor appears, the more competent and trustworthy the speaker seems.
🎯“Extended metaphors encourage belief fixation by accumulating examples that match the metaphorical construal.”➔ The strategic piling of metaphorical instances traps the audience into believing the underlying metaphor as truth.
Suggested Readings: “Metaphor as Argument: Rhetorical and Epistemic Advantages of Extended Metaphors” by Steve Oswald and Alain Rihs
  1. MÁCHA, JAKUB. “Metaphor in Analytic Philosophy and Cognitive Science.” Revista Portuguesa de Filosofia, vol. 75, no. 4, 2019, pp. 2247–86. JSTOR, https://www.jstor.org/stable/26869269. Accessed 26 Apr. 2025.
  2. Ervas, Francesca. “Metaphor, Ignorance and the Sentiment of (Ir)Rationality.” Synthese, vol. 198, no. 7, 2021, pp. 6789–813. JSTOR, https://www.jstor.org/stable/27293775. Accessed 26 Apr. 2025.
  3. Fitz John Porter Poole. “Metaphors and Maps: Towards Comparison in the Anthropology of Religion.” Journal of the American Academy of Religion, vol. 54, no. 3, 1986, pp. 411–57. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/1464561. Accessed 26 Apr. 2025.
  4. Winter, Steven L. “The Metaphor of Standing and the Problem of Self-Governance.” Stanford Law Review, vol. 40, no. 6, 1988, pp. 1371–516. JSTOR, https://doi.org/10.2307/1228780. Accessed 26 Apr. 2025.

“The Contemporary Theory Of Metaphor” by George Lakoff: Summary and Critique

“The Contemporary Theory of Metaphor” by George Lakoff first appeared in 1993 as a chapter in Metaphor and Thought, edited by Andrew Ortony and published by Cambridge University Press.

"The Contemporary Theory Of Metaphor" by George Lakoff: Summary and Critique
Introduction: “The Contemporary Theory Of Metaphor” by George Lakoff

“The Contemporary Theory of Metaphor” by George Lakoff first appeared in 1993 as a chapter in Metaphor and Thought, edited by Andrew Ortony and published by Cambridge University Press. This influential work reshaped both linguistic and literary theories of metaphor by shifting its focus from metaphor as a purely linguistic ornament to a fundamental mechanism of human thought. Lakoff challenges the classical view—traced back to Aristotle—that metaphor is merely a poetic or rhetorical device involving the novel use of words. Instead, he proposes that metaphors are cross-domain conceptual mappings deeply embedded in our cognitive processes and everyday language. For instance, expressions like “we’re at a crossroads in our relationship” or “time is flying” are not poetic anomalies but reflections of underlying metaphoric structures such as LOVE IS A JOURNEY or TIME IS MOTION. Lakoff demonstrates that these mappings are systematic and arise from embodied human experiences, thus blurring the rigid boundary between literal and figurative language. This theory has profoundly impacted cognitive linguistics, literary studies, and philosophy, highlighting that metaphor is not peripheral but central to meaning-making and abstract reasoning. Moreover, through detailed examples and references—such as Mark Turner’s Death Is the Mother of Beauty and the work of Michael Reddy—Lakoff reinforces that literary metaphors are extensions of conventional thought patterns, not departures from them. This cognitive approach to metaphor continues to influence modern discourse analysis, pedagogy, and the interpretation of literature.


Summary of “The Contemporary Theory Of Metaphor” by George Lakoff

🌟 Metaphor Is Primarily Conceptual, Not Linguistic

Lakoff challenges the classical view that metaphor is a matter of language, showing instead that it’s rooted in thought. Metaphors are cross-domain mappings in our conceptual system, not just rhetorical flourishes (Lakoff, 1987) 🧠. This reconceptualization moves metaphor from the poetic margins into the very core of everyday language use.

“The locus of metaphor is not in language at all, but in the way we conceptualize one mental domain in terms of another” (🌈 p. 203).


💡 Everyday Language Is Richly Metaphorical

Contrary to traditional views, Lakoff argues that ordinary language is saturated with metaphor. Expressions like “He fell in love” or “We’ve hit a dead-end” are not poetic but conventional and rooted in deeper conceptual structures. This finding dismantles the binary of “literal” vs. “figurative” language.

“Ordinary everyday English is largely metaphorical, dispelling once and for all the traditional view” (🟦 p. 204).


🚀 Conceptual Metaphor Theory: Cross-Domain Mappings

A conceptual metaphor maps a source domain (concrete) onto a target domain (abstract). For example, in LOVE IS A JOURNEY, the love relationship (target) is conceptualized in terms of a physical journey (source), as in: “Our relationship is off the track”.

“The metaphor involves understanding one domain of experience, love, in terms of a very different domain of experience, journeys” (💜 p. 207).


📘 Metaphors Govern Reasoning and Inference

Metaphors are not just expressive—they guide reasoning. When people say “We’re stuck in this relationship”, they rely on travel-related inferences (e.g., fixing a vehicle, turning back) to reason about love.

“Such correspondences permit us to reason about love using the knowledge we use to reason about journeys” (🧡 p. 208).


🌀 Metaphors Are Not Individual Words, but Cognitive Structures

Lakoff emphasizes that metaphors are not the words themselves but the mappings that sanction their use. Many metaphorical expressions stem from the same conceptual metaphor—e.g., dead-end, crossroads, off track—all from LOVE IS A JOURNEY.

“It is the ontological mapping across conceptual domains… the language is secondary” (💚 p. 209).


🔁 Basic Abstract Concepts Are Metaphorical

Even core concepts such as time, causation, states, purposes, and categories are metaphorically structured. For example:

  • TIME IS MOTION: “Christmas is coming up.”
  • CATEGORIES ARE CONTAINERS: “Put it in a different category.”

“Most basic concepts… are normally comprehended via metaphor—concepts like time, quantity, state, change…” (🟥 p. 213).


🛣️ Event Structure Is Metaphorically Understood

Lakoff introduces the EVENT STRUCTURE METAPHOR, where:

  • States = locations
  • Changes = movements
  • Causes = forces
  • Purposes = destinations

These structures govern expressions like “We’ve made it this far” or “We’re going nowhere”.

“States are locations… Causes are forces… Purposes are destinations” (💙 p. 221).


🧭 Metaphors Form Inheritance Hierarchies

Metaphors are organized hierarchically. For instance:

  1. EVENT STRUCTURE METAPHOR
  2. A PURPOSEFUL LIFE IS A JOURNEY
  3. LOVE IS A JOURNEY, CAREER IS A JOURNEY

Each lower level inherits from and is structured by the metaphor above it.

“The LOVE IS A JOURNEY metaphor inherits the structure of the LIFE IS A JOURNEY metaphor” (🟨 p. 224).


🔄 Duality: Location vs. Object-Based Metaphors

Every metaphor has a potential dual. For example:

  • STATES ARE LOCATIONS (e.g., in trouble)
  • ATTRIBUTES ARE POSSESSIONS (e.g., have trouble)

Both share the idea of co-location, highlighting how metaphorical thinking can take different structural forms.

“States and attributes are also special cases of the same thing—what can be attributed to someone” (🟪 p. 226).


🎨 Image Metaphors and the Invariance Principle

Image metaphors (like “Her waist is an hourglass”) map one mental image onto another. The Invariance Principle states that image-schematic structure (like paths or containers) is preserved in metaphoric mappings.

“The metaphor is conceptual; it is not in the words themselves, but in the mental images” (🔷 p. 230).


📚 Generic-Level Metaphors and Proverb Interpretation

Generic-level metaphors allow us to map specific instances to general structures, explaining how proverbs (e.g., “Blind blames the ditch”) work. They rely on preserved causal, temporal, and event schemas.

“Generic-level structure… is exactly image-schematic structure” (🔶 p. 234).


🧠 Abstract Reasoning Is Image-Based

Lakoff’s most radical conclusion is that abstract thought is grounded in image-schemas. Our capacity for logic and inference emerges from metaphorically extended spatial and bodily experience.

“Abstract reasoning is a special case of image-based reasoning” (⚫ p. 229).

Theoretical Terms/Concepts in “The Contemporary Theory Of Metaphor” by George Lakoff
🔖 Theoretical Term🧠 Explanation🛠️ Example / Usage with In-text Citation
🧭 Conceptual MetaphorSystematic mapping between two conceptual domains: source (concrete) → target (abstract).LOVE IS A JOURNEY → love is understood through the domain of journeys (Lakoff, p. 207).
📦 Source DomainThe domain from which metaphorical structure is drawn (concrete and familiar).In LOVE IS A JOURNEY, “journey” is the source domain (Lakoff, p. 207).
🎯 Target DomainThe abstract concept being understood through metaphor.In LOVE IS A JOURNEY, “love” is the target domain (Lakoff, p. 207).
🔁 Cross-Domain MappingSet of systematic correspondences between the source and target.Lovers → travelers, relationship → vehicle (Lakoff, p. 208).
🧩 Ontological CorrespondenceConceptual entity pairings between domains.Relationship difficulties = travel impediments (Lakoff, p. 208).
🔍 Epistemic CorrespondenceUse of source domain inferences to reason about the target domain.“We’re stuck” infers lack of progress in love using travel logic (Lakoff, p. 208).
🛠️ Metaphorical ExpressionThe actual linguistic expression stemming from a conceptual metaphor.“We’ve hit a dead-end street” is an expression from LOVE IS A JOURNEY (Lakoff, p. 209).
📘 Invariance PrincipleMetaphors preserve the image-schema structure of the source when mapping to the target.Containers → categories, paths → scales (Lakoff, p. 216).
🧠 Image SchemaFundamental spatial or bodily structures used in metaphor (e.g., container, path, force).“Out of gas” uses PATH and ENERGY schemas (Lakoff, p. 221).
🌐 Conceptual SystemThe entire network of metaphorical mappings in cognition.Everyday concepts like time and causation are metaphorical (Lakoff, p. 203).
🌀 Event Structure MetaphorAbstract events structured metaphorically using motion, force, and
Contribution of “The Contemporary Theory Of Metaphor” by George Lakoff to Literary Theory/Theories

🧠 1. Cognitive Literary Theory

🔍 Contribution: Lakoff radically repositions metaphor from a figure of speech to a core cognitive mechanism that shapes how we think, perceive, and reason—including in literature.
📌 Key Reference: “The locus of metaphor is not in language at all, but in the way we conceptualize one mental domain in terms of another.” (Lakoff, p. 203)
📚 Theoretical Connection: Supports Cognitive Poetics (Tsur, Stockwell) and Embodied Cognition in literary analysis, where metaphor is seen as structuring narrative and character psychology.


🧱 2. Structuralist & Post-Structuralist Revisions

🔁 Contribution: Challenges structuralist separation between literal and figurative language, asserting that everyday language is saturated with metaphor.
📌 Key Reference: “The discovery of this enormous metaphor system has destroyed the traditional literal-figurative distinction.” (Lakoff, p. 205)
📚 Theoretical Connection: Offers a post-structuralist critique of the arbitrary sign, suggesting metaphor is grounded in cognitive mappings, not in pure linguistic play.


🔄 3. Reframing Reader-Response Theory

👁️ Contribution: Emphasizes the reader’s conceptual system as key to interpreting metaphor—what readers “understand” is shaped by shared conceptual metaphors.
📌 Key Reference: “The metaphor is not just a matter of language, but of thought and reason.” (Lakoff, p. 209)
📚 Theoretical Connection: Enhances Reader-Response Theory (Fish, Iser) by adding a cognitive layer—interpretation arises from experiential metaphors, not just textual gaps or reader projection.


🎨 4. Enriching Poetic and Literary Analysis

🎭 Contribution: Shows that poetic metaphors, like those in Dylan Thomas or Wallace Stevens, are built upon conventional everyday mappings.
📌 Key Reference: “The study of literary metaphor is an extension of the study of everyday metaphor.” (Lakoff, p. 203)
📚 Theoretical Connection: Redefines Formalism/New Criticism by relocating metaphor’s richness from poetic novelty to cognitive familiarity; also bridges New Historicism, which examines how metaphor reflects broader cultural cognition.


🛠️ 5. Tool for Allegory and Symbolism Analysis

🔑 Contribution: Introduces conceptual metaphor mapping as a powerful analytic tool for understanding allegory, symbol, and myth.
📌 Key Reference: “There is a single general principle… part of the conceptual system underlying English.” (Lakoff, p. 208)
📚 Theoretical Connection: Useful for Myth Criticism (Frye, Campbell), understanding how symbolic narratives (e.g., life-as-journey) structure plot and character arcs.


🌉 6. Bridging Literature and Philosophy of Language

🔧 Contribution: Directly critiques philosophers like Searle and classical theories of metaphor, offering an empirically grounded alternative.
📌 Key Reference: “What we had called propositional structure is really image-based inference.” (Lakoff, p. 229)
📚 Theoretical Connection: Connects with Philosophy of Literature, challenging analytical distinctions between metaphor and truth-functional language.


🖼️ 7. Broadening Symbolic Interpretation in Literature

📐 Contribution: Introduces Image Metaphor (e.g., “her waist is an hourglass”) as a unique, non-propositional literary device rooted in visual-spatial cognition.
📌 Key Reference: “Image metaphors… map the structure of one domain onto the structure of another.” (Lakoff, p. 230)
📚 Theoretical Connection: Advances Iconic and Visual Theories of Literature, enhancing how we interpret symbolic and imagistic language beyond mere simile.


🌐 8. Foundation for Conceptual Narratology

🚶 Contribution: The Event Structure Metaphor (states = locations, causes = forces, goals = destinations) offers a way to analyze plot and narrative causality.
📌 Key Reference: “States are locations. Changes are movements… Purposes are destinations.” (Lakoff, p. 221)
📚 Theoretical Connection: Contributes to Narratology (Propp, Genette) by mapping narrative elements onto embodied experience.


🔄 9. Reorienting Tropes in Rhetoric and Style

🔁 Contribution: Demonstrates how metaphorical systems structure idioms, clichés, and stylistic expressions, revealing their deep cognitive roots.
📌 Key Reference: “Many of the metaphorical expressions… are idioms… not arbitrary, but motivated.” (Lakoff, p. 212)
📚 Theoretical Connection: Recontextualizes Classical Rhetoric and Stylistics, viewing them through the lens of cognitive motivation.


🧬 10. Expanding Theories of Symbolic Inheritance

🏗️ Contribution: Introduces metaphorical inheritance hierarchies (e.g., LOVE IS A JOURNEYLIFE IS A JOURNEYEVENT STRUCTURE), mapping complex cultural and literary motifs.
📌 Key Reference: “Metaphorical mappings do not occur isolated… they are organized in hierarchical structures.” (Lakoff, p. 223)
📚 Theoretical Connection: Aligns with Intertextuality and Archetypal Criticism, illuminating how metaphorical networks span genres and traditions.

Examples of Critiques Through “The Contemporary Theory Of Metaphor” by George Lakoff
📚 Literary Work🔁 Key Conceptual Metaphor(s)🔍 Lakoffian Critique & Interpretation
🌌 “Do Not Go Gentle into That Good Night” by Dylan ThomasDEATH IS NIGHT, LIFE IS A STRUGGLE, DEATH IS DEPARTUREThomas layers multiple metaphors to resist the passive acceptance of death. “Night” as metaphor for death draws on the LIFE IS A DAY schema, while STRUGGLE frames dying as an active, heroic resistance. (Lakoff, 1993)
🛤️ “The Road Not Taken” by Robert FrostLIFE IS A JOURNEY, CHOICES ARE PATHSFrost’s bifurcating paths represent life decisions. The metaphor activates cognitive mappings of DECISIONS AS TRAVEL, where direction and regret are structured spatially. (Lakoff, 1980)
🚖 “Because I Could Not Stop for Death” by Emily DickinsonDEATH IS A PERSON, DEATH IS A JOURNEYDickinson personifies death as a courteous suitor in a carriage—merging DEATH AS DEPARTURE with DEATH AS COMPANION, echoing Lakoff’s blend of EVENTS ARE ACTIONS and ABSTRACT IS CONCRETE.
🪞 “The Love Song of J. Alfred Prufrock” by T.S. EliotTIME IS A THIEF, LOVE IS A STRUGGLE/JOURNEY, SELF IS FRAGMENTED SPACEPrufrock’s paralysis is mapped through metaphorical inertia. The speaker’s internal fragmentation reflects spatial metaphors of disconnection and obstruction, reinforcing alienation. (Lakoff & Johnson, 1980)
Criticism Against “The Contemporary Theory Of Metaphor” by George Lakoff

🔴 🔍 Overemphasis on Universality
Lakoff’s theory assumes many metaphors (e.g., “TIME IS MOTION”, “LIFE IS A JOURNEY”) are universal, but cross-cultural linguistic studies show that metaphorical frameworks differ significantly between languages and cultures (e.g., in Chinese or Aymara, future is not always “ahead”).

🟡 🔄 Cognitive Reductionism
Critics argue the theory reduces complex literary or poetic expressions to fixed conceptual mappings, such as “LOVE IS A JOURNEY”, ignoring nuance, irony, and stylistic ambiguity present in creative literature.

🟠 🧱 Static Mapping Critique
The notion of fixed cross-domain mappings is criticized as too rigid. Real-life metaphor use often involves dynamic, context-sensitive constructions, not always aligning with pre-set metaphors.

🟢 📏 Inadequate Account of Novelty
While Lakoff acknowledges image metaphors and novel expressions, some scholars argue the theory underrepresents creative, one-off metaphorical innovations in literature and speech (cf. Ricoeur’s “living metaphors”).

🔵 📚 Neglect of Aesthetic Dimension
Lakoff’s focus is primarily cognitive and conceptual. Critics in literary theory (e.g., Eagleton) claim that this ignores the aesthetic, emotional, and cultural dimensions that make metaphor powerful in poetry and prose.

🟣 🧠 Challenges in Psychological Validation
Some psycholinguistic studies suggest that people don’t consistently rely on metaphorical reasoning in real-time understanding, challenging Lakoff’s claim that metaphor is central to everyday cognition (McGlone, 2007).

⚖️ Literal-Figurative Dichotomy Remains Debated
Although Lakoff dissolves the traditional literal vs. metaphorical distinction, other theorists argue some form of it remains useful, especially for distinguishing novel metaphors from conventional lexicalized expressions.

🟤 🖼️ Weakness in Explaining Visual/Multimodal Metaphor
Lakoff’s theory is primarily linguistic and does not robustly extend to visual, gestural, or multimodal metaphors, which are crucial in film, art, and digital media.

Representative Quotations from “The Contemporary Theory Of Metaphor” by George Lakoff with Explanation
🔹️ Quotation💡 Explanation📚 Citation
🔥“Metaphor is not just a matter of language, but of thought and reason.”Lakoff argues that metaphors are not merely decorative linguistic devices—they shape how we conceptualize the world.Lakoff, 1993, p. 208
🧠“The locus of metaphor is not in language at all, but in the way we conceptualize one mental domain in terms of another.”Metaphor is rooted in cognition—how our brain organizes and understands experiences.Lakoff, 1993, p. 203
🚗“Love is a journey.”This famous metaphor illustrates how abstract concepts (love) are understood via more concrete experiences (a journey).Lakoff, 1993, p. 206
🗺️“Conceptual metaphors are mappings from a source domain to a target domain.”Lakoff introduces the key mechanism of metaphorical mapping, which connects different conceptual areas.Lakoff, 1993, p. 207
💬“Metaphors are mappings, that is, sets of conceptual correspondences.”Clarifies that metaphor is not propositional (not a statement of truth) but relational.Lakoff, 1993, p. 208
🌍“Most of our conceptual system is metaphorical in nature.”Metaphors are pervasive, structuring everything from time to morality, not just poetic language.Lakoff, 1993, p. 210
🚧“Difficulties are impediments to motion.”Everyday metaphors (e.g., “we’re stuck”) come from embodied experiences, such as moving through space.Lakoff, 1993, p. 221
🧳“A purposeful life is a journey.”Life is metaphorically seen as travel toward goals—this structure is inherited from broader event metaphors.Lakoff, 1993, p. 223
📦“Classical categories are understood metaphorically in terms of bounded regions, or ‘containers.’”Even fundamental logical concepts like categories rely on spatial metaphors.Lakoff, 1993, p. 213
🧭“Abstract reasoning is a special case of image-based reasoning.”Suggests that even logic and reasoning stem from bodily experience and spatial imagination.Lakoff, 1993, p. 229
Suggested Readings: “The Contemporary Theory Of Metaphor” by George Lakoff
  1. Cornelissen, Joep P. “Beyond Compare: Metaphor in Organization Theory.” The Academy of Management Review, vol. 30, no. 4, 2005, pp. 751–64. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/20159166. Accessed 21 Apr. 2025.
  2. MÁCHA, JAKUB. “Metaphor in Analytic Philosophy and Cognitive Science.” Revista Portuguesa de Filosofia, vol. 75, no. 4, 2019, pp. 2247–86. JSTOR, https://www.jstor.org/stable/26869269. Accessed 21 Apr. 2025.
  3. Robinson, William E. W. “Metaphor Theory.” Metaphor, Morality, and the Spirit in Romans 8: 1–17, Society of Biblical Literature, 2016, pp. 17–44. JSTOR, https://doi.org/10.2307/j.ctt1h4mhzd.6. Accessed 21 Apr. 2025.
  4. Bilsky, Manuel. “I. A. Richards’ Theory of Metaphor.” Modern Philology, vol. 50, no. 2, 1952, pp. 130–37. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/435560. Accessed 21 Apr. 2025.

“Literature And Metaphor” By Earl R. Maccormac: Summary and Critique

“Literature and Metaphor” by Earl R. MacCormac first appeared in The Journal of Aesthetic Education, Volume 6, No. 3, published in July 1972 by the University of Illinois Press.

"Literature And Metaphor" By Earl R. Maccormac: Summary and Critique
Introduction: “Literature And Metaphor” By Earl R. Maccormac

“Literature and Metaphor” by Earl R. MacCormac first appeared in The Journal of Aesthetic Education, Volume 6, No. 3, published in July 1972 by the University of Illinois Press. It explores the foundational role of metaphor not only in literature but also across philosophy and science, challenging long-held assumptions about metaphor’s imprecision. MacCormac advances a “tension theory” of metaphor, distinguishing between two essential types—epiphors, which reveal analogical truths rooted in experience, and diaphors, which generate novel, imaginative meanings. He asserts that metaphors are not mere decorative devices but essential linguistic tools that shape understanding, especially when they evolve into root metaphors—underlying symbolic frameworks that structure entire works or even scientific paradigms. Through this lens, literature is shown to be a dynamic interplay of metaphorical meanings, not reducible to paraphrase or isolated symbol systems. MacCormac’s synthesis of philosophical and literary analysis has significantly influenced literary theory by affirming metaphor’s epistemological power, its capacity to innovate language, and its potential to reveal or obscure reality when mistaken as literal truth—a process he associates with the formation of myths. His work remains crucial for understanding metaphor as a central force in the creation and interpretation of literary meaning.

Summary of “Literature And Metaphor” By Earl R. Maccormac

🔹 Main Ideas of “Metaphor and Literature” by Earl R. MacCormac:

  • 📌 Metaphor is foundational to literature and creativity, acting as a crucial tool for expressing meaning beyond literal language. Literature without metaphor would become dull and unimaginative (⭑ MacCormac, 1972, p. 57).
  • 📌 Philosophical suspicion toward metaphor has lessened over time. While once seen as imprecise, metaphor is now recognized as essential in both philosophy and science (⭑ p. 57–58).
  • 📌 Scientific concepts like “force” or “mass” are metaphors and are not linguistically precise terms, highlighting metaphor’s role in the formation of theories (✦ p. 58).
  • 📌 MacCormac proposes a “tension theory of metaphor,” where meaning arises from the tension between literal absurdity and figurative insight. Metaphor creates a moment of disruption that compels the reader to reflect “as if” the statement were true (⭒ p. 59).
  • 📌 The article differentiates two types of metaphor:
    • Epiphor: based on analogy; reveals hidden but relatable meanings (✧ p. 60).
    • Diaphor: introduces new, often imaginative meanings that cannot be reduced to familiar analogies (✧ p. 61).
  • 📌 Metaphors evolve: they may begin as diaphors, become expressive epiphors, and ultimately turn into dead metaphors or symbols in ordinary language (⭐ p. 62).
  • 📌 MacCormac introduces the concept of “root metaphors”—deep metaphoric structures (e.g., “the world is a machine”) that underlie entire philosophical or literary worldviews. These root metaphors shape how entire texts or scientific paradigms are interpreted (✪ p. 63–64).
  • 📌 Myths arise when root metaphors are taken literally. Myths can be found in science, literature, religion, and philosophy when hypothetical metaphors are mistaken for truth (✹ p. 67–69).
  • 📌 Symbols in literature are born from metaphors, especially epiphors, and become emotionally charged archetypal symbols through repetition (✸ p. 64–66).
  • 📌 Metaphors should be understood as linguistic symbols, not just psychological phenomena. Reducing all metaphor to cognitive response oversimplifies their structural role in meaning-making (✦ p. 66).
  • 📌 The article calls for a critical awareness of metaphor’s role in constructing meaning, cautioning against confusing metaphorical frameworks with literal reality (✴ p. 69–70).

🔍 Implications for Literary Criticism (per MacCormac):

  • ✅ Metaphors cannot be paraphrased without losing their unique meanings—especially diaphors (✦ p. 70).
  • Root metaphors and conveyance metaphors must be distinguished. The former underlie whole works; the latter function within narratives (✪ p. 64).
  • ✅ Ordinary language itself is built from dead metaphors, highlighting how pervasive and foundational metaphor is in human thought (✦ p. 60).
  • Myths should not be eliminated outright, but critically examined as historically contingent metaphorical systems (✹ p. 68).
  • ✅ Literary meaning is not solely internal to the text—reader experience and broader metaphorical structures also inform interpretation (✧ p. 64–65).
Theoretical Terms/Concepts in “Literature And Metaphor” By Earl R. Maccormac
Term/ConceptUsage in the Article (with citation)Explanation
MetaphorDefined as a “juxtaposition of words” that produces literal absurdity and invites new meaning (MacCormac, 1972, p. 59).A core linguistic device used to express or suggest meanings beyond the literal through imaginative association.
Tension TheoryMacCormac’s central theory: metaphor functions through the tension between literal absurdity and figurative insight (p. 59).Metaphor creates meaning by presenting an unexpected or absurd juxtaposition that demands reinterpretation.
EpiphorA metaphor grounded in analogy and expressiveness, e.g., “I see the point” (p. 60–61).A metaphor that expresses an existing insight or experience in a vivid, novel way.
DiaphorMetaphors that suggest new, often imaginative meanings with no prior analog, e.g., Dryden’s depiction of nature (p. 61–62).A metaphor that introduces unfamiliar concepts, often irreducible to existing knowledge or ordinary language.
Root MetaphorFoundational metaphors like “the world is a machine” that underlie entire works or theories (p. 63–64).Deep metaphoric structures shaping entire systems of meaning, such as literary works or scientific paradigms.
MythOccurs when root metaphors are mistaken as literal truths, such as in science or religion (p. 67–69).A belief system that results from interpreting metaphorical expressions as factual reality.
Ordinary LanguageUsed to identify metaphors; contrasts with metaphor’s deviation from everyday usage (p. 60).Common, everyday language used as the benchmark for recognizing metaphorical tension or deviation.
Dead MetaphorMetaphors that lose tension through habitual use, e.g., “I see the point” (p. 61).Expressions originally metaphorical that become part of ordinary discourse and lose figurative force.
Archetypal SymbolEmotionally resonant symbols derived from metaphors, e.g., water for life (p. 64–65).Universally recurring symbols in literature with strong emotional or cultural associations.
Symbol (Linguistic)All words are symbols; metaphors operate through these symbolic units (p. 65–66).Words that convey meaning through denotation, connotation, and subjective association; fundamental to metaphor.
SignContrasted with symbols; a direct indicator, like smoke for fire (p. 66).A non-linguistic or immediate indicator lacking the layered meaning of a symbol.
“As If” QualityMetaphors make us think “as if” something were literally true, e.g., “build in sonnets pretty rooms” (p. 59).A hallmark of metaphor that involves imagining a literal absurdity as if it were real, revealing deeper insight.
Internal MeaningCritiques Frye’s view that meaning exists only within the text’s own metaphoric system (p. 64).The idea that texts are self-contained in meaning, which MacCormac challenges by emphasizing reader interpretation and context.
Symbol FormationProcess where metaphors, through repetition, become symbols or archetypes (p. 66).The transformation of metaphorical expressions into culturally or literarily fixed symbolic forms.
Contribution of “Literature And Metaphor” By Earl R. Maccormac to Literary Theory/Theories

🧠 1. Structuralism

  • 🔹 Emphasizes that metaphor is a linguistic structure that organizes meaning through patterns and associations (⭑ MacCormac, 1972, p. 59).
  • 🔹 Introduces the concept that ordinary language is structured by “dead metaphors”, showing how metaphors shape language systems (⭑ p. 60).
  • 🔹 By analyzing metaphor as a structured interaction between “tenor” and “vehicle” (Richards), the article aligns with structuralist focus on binary relationships (✦ p. 59).

🔮 2. Reader-Response Theory

  • 🔹 Argues that the recognition of metaphor depends on the reader’s awareness of absurdity and interpretive ability (✧ p. 59).
  • 🔹 Claims that metaphors gain meaning only through the reader’s ability to imagine or connect to experience, especially in the case of diaphors (✧ p. 61–62).
  • 🔹 Suggests that interpretive response is essential to moving metaphors from tension to comprehension (✧ p. 62).

📘 3. Formalism / New Criticism

  • 🔹 Acknowledges the internal function of metaphor in constructing literary unity, especially when rooted in a dominant image (✪ p. 63).
  • 🔹 Discusses metaphors that carry the thematic structure of a work (root metaphors), which are central to formalist close reading (✪ p. 64).
  • 🔹 Challenges New Criticism slightly by arguing that not all meaning is internally contained within a work’s structure (✪ p. 64–65).

🌍 4. Phenomenology / Hermeneutics

  • 🔹 Describes metaphor as an experiential bridge, where the reader’s own perception fills the gap between literal absurdity and figurative meaning (✸ p. 59–60).
  • 🔹 Suggests that understanding metaphor is a phenomenological act that involves the transformation of experience into insight (✸ p. 61).
  • 🔹 Root metaphors provide hermeneutic frameworks for interpreting literary worlds and philosophical systems (✸ p. 63–64).

🧬 5. Post-Structuralism / Deconstruction

  • 🔹 Identifies the instability of meaning in metaphors—especially diaphors—which resist paraphrase and final interpretation (✴ p. 70).
  • 🔹 Argues that literal and figurative are not absolute categories, since dead metaphors blur the boundary (✴ p. 60–61).
  • 🔹 Challenges the idea of a stable referent, showing that metaphor often undermines the clarity of language (✴ p. 69).

📚 6. Archetypal and Symbolic Criticism

  • 🔹 Tracks how metaphors evolve into archetypal symbols with emotional resonance, e.g., “water” representing life (✹ p. 64–65).
  • 🔹 Connects metaphor to universal human expressions, consistent with Jungian and mythological criticism (✹ p. 65).

⚙️ 7. Philosophy of Language / Analytic Literary Theory

  • 🔹 Contributes to theoretical philosophy of metaphor, extending ideas of Max Black and I.A. Richards into literary application (⭑ p. 59).
  • 🔹 Discusses metaphor in terms of linguistic functions, meaning variance, and ostension (⭑ p. 60; ⭑ p. 61).
  • 🔹 Establishes that literary and philosophical language share metaphorical logic, rejecting strict literalism in analytic traditions (⭑ p. 67).

🧱 8. Myth Criticism

  • 🔹 Defines myth as a literalized root metaphor, warning that myth arises when metaphor is mistaken as objective truth (✦ p. 67–69).
  • 🔹 Suggests that myths pervade all fields, from literature to science, when metaphor is misinterpreted as fact (✦ p. 69).
  • 🔹 Encourages a critical approach to metaphor to avoid mythologizing knowledge and ideology (✦ p. 69–70).
Examples of Critiques Through “Literature And Metaphor” By Earl R. Maccormac
Literary WorkCritique Through MacCormac’s TheoryKey Concepts & Symbols
🕯️ John Donne – The CanonizationThe line “We’ll build in sonnets pretty rooms” exemplifies a diaphor, as it juxtaposes physical construction with poetic form, forcing imaginative interpretation (MacCormac, p. 59).🔹 Diaphor 🔸 Tension Theory ✴ “As If” Quality
🌳 Robert Frost – A Hillside ThawFrost’s metaphors (“The sun’s a wizard… the moon a witch”) are strong diaphors that propose fresh, non-literal realities that stretch the reader’s perception (MacCormac, p. 62).🔹 Diaphor ✴ Symbol Formation 🔸 Myth Potential
🎻 John Dryden – A Song for St. Cecilia’s DayDryden’s metaphor of nature lying under “jarring atoms” serves as a root metaphor, combining poetic form with early scientific theory; suggests a worldview, not just an image (p. 61–63).⚙️ Root Metaphor 🔸 Myth Criticism ✴ Diaphoric Suggestiveness
⚔️ William Shakespeare – MacbethThe recurring metaphor of darkness (“Stars, hide your fires”) may begin as a diaphor, but becomes an archetypal symbol of moral blindness and ambition (interpreted via p. 64–66).✹ Archetypal Symbol 🔹 Epiphor ➡ Dead Metaphor 🔸 Symbolic Transformation
Criticism Against “Literature And Metaphor” By Earl R. Maccormac

Criticisms Against “Literature and Metaphor” by Earl R. MacCormac:

  • ⚖️ Overemphasis on Philosophy Over Literary Practice
    ▪️ MacCormac heavily draws from philosophical traditions (e.g., Aristotle, Max Black, Stephen Pepper), sometimes sidelining close textual analysis or literary nuance.
    ▪️ Critics may argue that this makes the theory less practical for analyzing complex literary texts in detail.
  • 🌀 Ambiguity Between Epiphor and Diaphor
    ▪️ The distinction between epiphor (based on analogy) and diaphor (suggesting new meaning) is insightful but can become conceptually blurry.
    ▪️ In many cases, metaphors contain elements of both, making rigid classification difficult (⭑ MacCormac, 1972, p. 61–62).
  • 🧩 Lack of Engagement with Historical or Cultural Contexts
    ▪️ The theory largely treats metaphor as a universal linguistic process, neglecting how cultural, historical, or socio-political factors shape metaphor usage and reception.
  • 🗺️ Limited Scope of Literary Examples
    ▪️ The article relies mostly on Western canon examples (e.g., Donne, Frost, Dryden), potentially narrowing its cross-cultural applicability.
    ▪️ It does not test the theory on non-Western or postmodern literature where metaphor might function differently.
  • 🏗️ Abstract Treatment of Myth and Reality
    ▪️ MacCormac’s claim that myths are merely literalized root metaphors (p. 67–69) could be seen as reductive.
    ▪️ It overlooks the deeper symbolic, religious, or communal functions of myth in human culture.
  • 🔄 Resistance to Internal Meaning Theories
    ▪️ MacCormac challenges Northrop Frye’s idea of internal literary meaning (p. 64), but his alternative may not satisfy formalists who value textual coherence and self-containment.
    ▪️ Some may argue that he dismisses valid interpretive strategies too quickly.
  • 🔍 Insufficient Practical Methodology for Criticism
    ▪️ The article offers a theoretical framework but lacks clear, repeatable steps for applying it in literary criticism.
    ▪️ Readers may struggle to operationalize his concepts without more methodological guidance.
  • 💬 Minimal Dialogue with Contemporary Literary Theorists
    ▪️ While the work is grounded in philosophical and linguistic traditions, it engages less with contemporary literary theorists (e.g., Barthes, Derrida, Eagleton), missing inter-theoretical dialogue.

🧠 Summary:

While “Literature and Metaphor” is foundational in positioning metaphor at the center of meaning-making in literature, its philosophical abstraction, binary metaphor classifications, and lack of cultural contextualization leave room for criticism. Scholars seeking more culturally grounded, politically aware, or text-specific analysis may find MacCormac’s framework limited in scope.

Representative Quotations from “Literature And Metaphor” By Earl R. Maccormac with Explanation
QuotationExplanation Citation
“Literature without metaphor would become less imaginative and poetry would be so impaired as to become dull and perhaps even trite.”Emphasizes the essential role of metaphor in preserving creativity and vitality in literary works.(MacCormac, 1972, p. 57)
“A metaphor consists of a juxtaposition of words that when read literally produces absurdity.”Introduces the “tension theory” of metaphor, suggesting that the clash with literal meaning creates interpretive tension.(MacCormac, 1972, p. 58)
“Ordinary language is filled with dead metaphors… metaphors that are no longer vibrant and filled with tension.”Highlights how metaphors can become normalized over time, losing their initial figurative power.(MacCormac, 1972, p. 60)
“Some diaphors do suggest ideas that we later do experience, and when they do so they become expressive and can be classed as epiphors.”Differentiates between diaphors (new/suggestive metaphors) and epiphors (analogous/expressive ones).(MacCormac, 1972, p. 61)
“The world is not completely mathematical nor is it fully a machine, and these root metaphors always retain a tensive quality.”Argues that root metaphors, even when influential (e.g., in science), are never fully explanatory or literal.(MacCormac, 1972, p. 63)
“Metaphoric meaning is not solely contained within a literary structure.”Challenges structuralist views that limit interpretation to internal elements, emphasizing reader interaction.(MacCormac, 1972, p. 64)
“Archetypal symbols… express their meaning by the emotional association of concepts, objects, or situations.”Explains how archetypal symbols evolve from metaphors, gaining universal emotional meaning.(MacCormac, 1972, p. 65)
“Diaphors create new meaning and not just a psychological effect of absurdity.”Asserts that metaphors can be conceptually generative, not just aesthetically surprising.(MacCormac, 1972, p. 66)
“Root metaphors that are taken literally create myths which are dangerous and misleading.”Warns against mistaking metaphoric models (especially in science or religion) as literal truths.(MacCormac, 1972, p. 67)
“To call these speculations final is to become dogmatic and to create a myth.”Encourages critical awareness of the provisional and metaphorical nature of all explanatory frameworks.(MacCormac, 1972, p. 70)
Suggested Readings: “Literature And Metaphor” By Earl R. Maccormac
  1. MacCormac, Earl R. “Metaphor and Literature.” Journal of Aesthetic Education, vol. 6, no. 3, 1972, pp. 57–70. JSTOR, https://doi.org/10.2307/3331393. Accessed 21 Apr. 2025.
  2. Sobolev, Dennis. “Metaphor Revisited.” New Literary History, vol. 39, no. 4, 2008, pp. 903–29. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/20533122. Accessed 21 Apr. 2025.
  3. MÁCHA, JAKUB. “Metaphor in Analytic Philosophy and Cognitive Science.” Revista Portuguesa de Filosofia, vol. 75, no. 4, 2019, pp. 2247–86. JSTOR, https://www.jstor.org/stable/26869269. Accessed 21 Apr. 2025.
  4. Davis, Cynthia J. “Contagion as Metaphor.” American Literary History, vol. 14, no. 4, 2002, pp. 828–36. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/3568026. Accessed 21 Apr. 2025.

“Metaphor And Literary Comprehension” By Gerard Steen: Summary and Critique

“Metaphor and Literary Comprehension” by Gerard Steen first appeared in Poetics, Volume 18, in 1989 (pp. 113–141, North-Holland).

"Metaphor And Literary Comprehension" By Gerard Steen: Summary and Critique
Introduction: “Metaphor And Literary Comprehension” By Gerard Steen

“Metaphor and Literary Comprehension” by Gerard Steen first appeared in Poetics, Volume 18, in 1989 (pp. 113–141, North-Holland). Steen proposes a comprehensive discourse-theoretical framework for understanding metaphor in literary texts. He distinguishes three major functions of metaphor—expressive, transactional, and interactional—which align with the three dimensions of discourse: linguistic, cognitive, and communicative. A central concern of the essay is how the literary status of discourse alters the cognitive processing of metaphor. Steen contends that the reader’s literary attitude, shaped by socio-cultural conventions like the Esthetic (E) and Polyvalence (P) conventions, fundamentally transforms the way metaphors are identified, comprehended, and appreciated. He builds on models from cognitive psychology and literary theory (notably the Empirical Study of Literature, or ESL) to argue that metaphor understanding in literature is not merely a linguistic or stylistic feature but a dynamic cognitive event shaped by reading context and reader behavior. Importantly, Steen proposes testable hypotheses distinguishing implicit and explicit metaphor processing in readers, contributing to empirical literary research and bridging a gap between cognitive science and literary theory. His essay remains vital for scholars interested in metaphor, literary pragmatics, and discourse processing, asserting that metaphor in literature is both a site of cognitive richness and a reflection of deeper socio-cultural reading practices.

Summary of “Metaphor And Literary Comprehension” By Gerard Steen

🔍 Discourse-Theoretical Approach to Metaphor

  • 🧩 Metaphor must be understood within the broader framework of discourse, which encompasses language (text), cognition (comprehension), and communication (social interaction).

“Discourse can be treated as a congeries of three kinds of structures… language, cognition, and communication” (p. 115).
✳️


🎭 Three Functions of Metaphor

  • 💬 Expressive function (linguistic): Metaphor serves as a formal device to concisely express what would otherwise be lengthy or indirect.

“‘Julia is the sun’ is formally much more pointed than the lengthy alternatives” (p. 119).
✍️

  • 🧠 Transactional function (cognitive): Metaphor helps us relate and understand conceptual domains that are typically unrelated.

“Lovers are not often seen in terms of heavenly bodies, excusez le mot, but Shakespeare manages…” (p. 119).
🧠

  • 🤝 Interactional function (communicative): Metaphors influence the flow and interpretation of communication, shaped by genre and social context.

“This force may be vivid or flat, surprising or banal… esthetically pleasing or displeasing” (p. 119).
📡


📖 Literary vs. Non-Literary Reading

  • 🧾 Understanding metaphors is shaped by the type of discourse—literary or non-literary—and the attitude of reading the reader adopts.

“Understanding metaphor in a literary way may be highly influenced by the adoption of a literary attitude of reading” (p. 114).
🎭

  • 🧠 A literary attitude activates Esthetic (E) and Polyvalence (P) conventions, focusing on multiple meanings and aesthetic value rather than factual clarity.

“The Esthetic convention… implies the suspension of criteria such as true/false… The Polyvalence convention induces subjectively satisfactory comprehension processes…” (p. 123).
🌀


🔁 Role of Analogical Processing

  • 🔗 Analogy is central to metaphor comprehension in literature, where it is not just a problem-solving tool but a method of layered interpretation.

“The principle of analogy… is explosively exploited rather than restricted [in literature]” (p. 125).
🧪

  • 🧙 Allegory is seen as extended metaphorical analogy, but not all literary metaphors are allegorical.

“Allegory… has two separate meanings rather than one… metaphor also may have more clearly or vaguely distinct meanings than one” (p. 130).
🔍


🧩 Polyvalence of Literary Metaphor

  • 🎨 Literary metaphors tend to be polyvalent—open to multiple interpretations—due to vehicle elaboration and contextual layering.

“Polyvalence in literary metaphor may be due to… a series of vehicle interpretations” (p. 128).
🧷

  • 🧠 This results in a richer, multidimensional understanding as readers extract overlapping or even conflicting meanings.

“Metaphors may be refunctionalized as literary signs… producing symbolism and other effects” (p. 130).
🔮


🧭 Identification, Comprehension, and Appreciation

  • 📌 Steen proposes a three-part model of how metaphors are processed:
    1. Identification – Recognizing the presence of a metaphor
    2. Comprehension – Constructing meaning
    3. Appreciation – Valuing or evaluating the metaphor

“Identification of metaphor may be… metatextual elaboration… comprehension may lead to… alternative frames… appreciation may be part of polyvalent elaborations” (p. 134).
🔍🧠💖


🔄 Explicit vs. Implicit Processing

  • 👀 Steen distinguishes between explicit and implicit versions of all three processes, arguing that literary reading fosters explicit awareness of metaphor.

“Explicit identification… a meta-statement concerning the perceived metaphorical nature…” (p. 136).
⚖️

  • 📢 For example, explicit vehicle interpretation (recognizing and analyzing the metaphor’s source domain) is more likely in literary contexts.

“Experienced readers… emphasize vehicle interpretation… inexperienced readers tend to overlook this aspect” (p. 137).
🧭


🧪 Empirical and Cognitive Approach

  • 🧬 Steen emphasizes the need for empirical testing of his hypotheses via cognitive psychology (e.g., think-aloud protocols) and interdisciplinary work.

“Such obstacles need not prevent us… from both formulating tentative programs of research…” (p. 139).
📊

  • 🧑‍🔬 He encourages bridging gaps between psychological models of language comprehension and literary theory, advocating for discourse-based analysis.

“Many metaphors in literary texts need not be understood in a literary way… hence a general discourse theory is required…” (p. 139).
🧠🔗📚

Theoretical Terms/Concepts in “Metaphor And Literary Comprehension” By Gerard Steen
📘 Theoretical Term 📖 Explanation📎 Reference from Article
Discourse Theory 🔀A multi-dimensional approach to language involving linguistic (textual), cognitive, and communicative structures.“All discourse can be treated as a congeries of three kinds of structures… language, cognition, and communication” (p. 115).
Expressive Function 🗣The linguistic function of metaphor as a compact and evocative form of formal expression.“Language as a formal entity has only one function in discourse, i.e. an expressive one” (p. 117).
Transactional Function 🧠The cognitive role of metaphor in creating conceptual links between unrelated domains.“The direct connection… between two conceptual entities or domains…” (p. 119).
Interactional Function 🤝The social/communicative impact of metaphor—how it shapes relationships and discourse tone.“Its role in the domain of literary or non-literary communication” (p. 119).
E and P Conventions 🎨📚Esthetic (E) and Polyvalence (P) reading conventions that frame literary interpretation.“The Esthetic convention… The Polyvalence convention…” (p. 123).
Literary Attitude of Reading 🎭A cognitive mode of reading marked by openness to metaphor, ambiguity, and deeper engagement.“Understanding metaphor in a literary way… influenced by the adoption of a literary attitude of reading” (p. 114).
Analogical Processing 🔗Reasoning strategy that draws comparisons between domains; essential for metaphor interpretation.“The principle of analogy… is explosively exploited rather than restricted [in literature]” (p. 125).
Metaphorical Analogy 🔍Analogical comparison between dissimilar domains that underpins metaphor formation.“Metaphorical analogies do not involve terms from similar domains” (p. 126).
Allegory 🏛️An extended metaphor or analogy with two structurally distinct yet connected layers of meaning.“Allegory… has two separate meanings rather than one…” (p. 130).
Polyvalence 🌀The literary feature where multiple interpretations of a metaphor (or text) coexist.“Polyvalence in literary metaphor may be due to… a series of vehicle interpretations” (p. 128).
Vehicle Interpretation 🚗Cognitive processing of the metaphor’s source domain to evoke layered or image-rich meanings.“Vehicle interpretation… necessary to invoke the image aspect of the metaphor” (p. 127).
Focus Interpretation 🎯Interpretation focused on the metaphor’s topic without extending to the vehicle/source domain.“Metaphor in literature is characterized by explicit vehicle-interpretation…” (p. 127).
Explicit vs. Implicit Processing 👀🤔Differentiates between conscious (explicit) and subconscious (implicit) identification, understanding, and judgment.“Two cognitive types of identification… explicit and implicit…” (p. 136).
Identification, Comprehension, Appreciation 🔎🧩❤The three core cognitive steps in processing metaphor: recognizing, interpreting, and evaluating it.“The three related processes… composing the cognitive function of metaphor” (p. 120, also p. 133).
Textual Surface Strategy 📜A literary reading tactic focusing on formal features like style, diction, and metaphor for deeper meaning.“Point of view, tone, diction, and style… metaphor should be included in this list” (p. 124).
Figurative Event A fictional realization of metaphor within the text’s world, blending literal and figurative meaning.“Turns a clock metaphor for God into a giant clock that is a real danger…” (p. 130).
Double Vision 👓Simultaneous awareness of both literal and metaphorical meanings in a single expression.“Double perception of floating on the waves and riding a horse” (p. 127).
Contribution of “Metaphor And Literary Comprehension” By Gerard Steen to Literary Theory/Theories

🔀 📚 Discourse Theory Expansion

  • Contribution: Steen integrates metaphor into a three-dimensional discourse model (language, cognition, communication), broadening literary theory beyond structuralist/textual confines.
  • Reference: “All discourse can be treated as a congeries of three kinds of structures… language, cognition, and communication” (p. 115).
  • Theory Link: Enriches Discourse Analysis and Text Linguistics in literature by aligning with Prague Structuralism and socio-cognitive frameworks.

🎭 🧠 Reader-Response Theory Enrichment

  • Contribution: Emphasizes reader’s active construction of meaning in metaphor interpretation, especially through the E and P conventions.
  • Reference: “Understanding metaphor in a literary way may be highly influenced by the adoption of a literary attitude of reading” (p. 114).
  • Theory Link: Deepens Reader-Response Criticism by introducing attitudinal variation in metaphor recognition and appreciation.

🌀 📖 Empirical Literary Studies (ESL) Advancement

  • Contribution: Positions metaphor within the Empirical Study of Literature (ESL), promoting testable hypotheses and reader-based research.
  • Reference: “The ESL theory of understanding literary texts… offers some opportunities… for locating metaphor in literary discourse” (p. 114).
  • Theory Link: Aligns with Siegfried Schmidt’s ESL framework and supports experimental psychology in literary studies.

🔗 💬 Cognitive Poetics and Stylistics

  • Contribution: Introduces analogical processing as central to literary metaphor interpretation, bridging psychology and poetics.
  • Reference: “Analogical processing… is responsible for the specifically literary comprehension of metaphor” (p. 114).
  • Theory Link: Builds on Cognitive Poetics, reinforcing metaphor as a tool for mental model construction and not just rhetorical flourish.

🔍 🎯 Structuralist vs. Post-Structuralist Dialogue

  • Contribution: While grounded in form (structure), Steen critiques pure formalism by emphasizing reader agency, function, and polyvalence.
  • Reference: “Not all metaphors in literature are understood in a literary way by definition…” (p. 139).
  • Theory Link: Offers a bridge between Structuralist poetics (e.g., Jakobson) and Post-Structuralist variability.

🤝 📜 Literary Pragmatics Integration

  • Contribution: Reframes metaphor as a pragmatic device influenced by social context, genre expectations, and communicative conventions.
  • Reference: “The social function of metaphor… is achieved by the adherence to general literary discourse conventions” (p. 132).
  • Theory Link: Strengthens Literary Pragmatics, connecting with work by Jonathan Culler and Van Peer.

👀 🧩 Reception Theory: Micro-Processes Focus

  • Contribution: Introduces granular distinctions—explicit vs. implicit identification, comprehension, and appreciation—in metaphor reception.
  • Reference: “We need to distinguish between the implicit and explicit identification… comprehension… appreciation” (p. 138).
  • Theory Link: Adds psychological nuance to Reception Theory by tracking real-time cognitive behavior during reading.

⚙️ 🔄 Methodological Contribution to Literary Theories

  • Contribution: Proposes a methodologically rigorous, interdisciplinary approach combining psycholinguistics, discourse theory, and empirical testing.
  • Reference: “Such obstacles need not prevent us… from formulating tentative programs of research” (p. 139).
  • Theory Link: Catalyzes a research-based turn in literary theory, moving beyond speculative criticism.
Examples of Critiques Through “Metaphor And Literary Comprehension” By Gerard Steen
📘 Literary Work🧠 Steenian Critique Focus
🧝‍♂️ The Lord of the Rings by J.R.R. TolkienMetaphors like “the Ring” function as polyvalent literary signs. Through Steen’s E and P conventions, readers engage in analogical interpretation that uncovers layered moral, political, and existential meanings.
🐋 Moby-Dick by Herman MelvilleThe whale acts as a metaphorical domain inviting analogical reasoning. A literary attitude foregrounds its cognitive tension as both a natural being and metaphysical symbol, embodying Steen’s expressive and transactional discourse functions.
📜 The Love Song of J. Alfred Prufrock by T.S. EliotSteen’s concept of vehicle interpretation explains the metaphor “I have measured out my life with coffee spoons” as a double-vision moment, fusing mundane imagery with existential despair.
🐎 The Old Man and the Sea by Ernest HemingwayThe metaphor of the marlin and sea becomes allegorical under a literary attitude, aligning with Steen’s discourse theory. Holyoak’s analogical reading expands the struggle into metaphors of artistry, dignity, and mortality.
Criticism Against “Metaphor And Literary Comprehension” By Gerard Steen

🔍 Over-Theorization Without Empirical Evidence
While Steen emphasizes empirical methodology, the paper remains largely theoretical. Critics may argue that Steen falls short of offering actual data to validate his discourse-functional claims (Steen, 1989).

🧩 Ambiguity in Discourse Typology
The tripartite model of expressive, transactional, and interactional discourse functions may be seen as overlapping or too loosely defined, especially when applied across diverse literary genres.

⚖️ Lack of Engagement with Post-Structuralism
Steen’s cognitive approach is rooted in formalist and psychological models, which can appear reductive or incompatible with post-structuralist or deconstructive theories that resist fixed interpretation or “functions” of language.

🎭 Neglect of Cultural and Historical Context
Critics might argue that the model downplays the role of socio-historical context in shaping metaphorical meaning, focusing instead on cognitive processing as if it were universal and ahistorical.

🧠 Cognitive Bias and Reader Homogenization
The psychological framing assumes a somewhat uniform cognitive process across readers, which may ignore diverse interpretive communities or the variability of reader responses rooted in identity and context.

📚 Insufficient Focus on Non-Metaphorical Literary Devices
By centering metaphor, the paper potentially marginalizes other poetic and rhetorical strategies equally central to literary comprehension, such as irony, metonymy, or ambiguity.

🌀 Conflation of Literary Attitude and Literary Value
Steen’s reliance on the E and P conventions implies that readers can “switch on” a literary mode of reading. Critics may question whether such a clean switch exists, or whether this oversimplifies how texts are actually read and valued.


 Representative Quotations from “Metaphor And Literary Comprehension” By Gerard Steen with Explanation
🔖 Quotation📘 Explanation
🌟 “Three important functions of metaphor are distinguished: the expressive, the transactional and the interactional…” (p. 113)This foundational classification anchors metaphor in discourse theory. Expressive refers to formal expression, transactional to cognition, and interactional to communicative impact.
💬 “The assumption of a difference between a linguistic and a cognitive side to metaphor is precisely why it is necessary to distinguish between three functions…” (p. 117)Steen stresses the importance of separating metaphor’s linguistic form from its cognitive and social effects, allowing a multidimensional approach to metaphor analysis.
🔍 “Metaphor is a formal entity belonging to the domain of text… a potential formal stimulus on the behaviour of readers.” (p. 117)This defines metaphor not only as a textual feature but as a stimulus for reader engagement, paving the way for empirical study.
🎭 “Literary comprehension is approached as a special and specific subtype of understanding metaphor in general…” (p. 118)Steen positions literary reading as a specialized discourse behavior, shaped by cultural conventions like the Esthetic (E) and Polyvalence (P) conventions.
🧠 “Understanding metaphor in literature may be highly influenced by the adoption of a literary attitude of reading…” (p. 118)This quotation highlights how reader attitude, shaped by context and genre, plays a critical role in how metaphors are processed in literary texts.
🧭 “We assume that the understanding of metaphor in literary texts is influenced by the adoption of a literary attitude of reading.” (p. 123)The cognitive response to metaphor is not fixed but depends on whether readers approach the text literarily or non-literarily.
⚖️ “Explicit identification will be investigated as the attribution of a meta-statement concerning the perceived metaphorical nature…” (p. 136)Steen emphasizes the difference between implicit and explicit recognition of metaphor, which helps empirically analyze how metaphors are processed.
🌀 “Polyvalence in literary metaphor may be due to a literary exploitation of the implications arising from a single metaphorical statement.” (p. 128)Steen explains how multiple interpretations from one metaphor are a hallmark of literary reading, driven by the polyvalence convention.
🎨 “The polyvalent nature of literary meaning… is what makes literary allegory such a rich store of meaning…” (p. 127)Allegory is shown to function like metaphor on a broader scale, allowing for multiple simultaneous interpretations in literary discourse.
🔬 “Empirical research in understanding metaphor in literary texts needs to be grounded in a discourse theory of metaphor.” (p. 139)The closing argument affirms the essay’s goal: to bridge empirical study and literary theory via a systematic discourse-based framework.
Suggested Readings: “Metaphor And Literary Comprehension” By Gerard Steen
  1. Steen, Gerard. “Literary and Nonliterary Aspects of Metaphor.” Poetics Today, vol. 13, no. 4, 1992, pp. 687–704. JSTOR, https://doi.org/10.2307/1773294. Accessed 16 Apr. 2025.
  2. Steen, Gerard. “Metaphor and literary comprehension: Towards a discourse theory of metaphor in literature.” Poetics 18.1-2 (1989): 113-141.

“The Motive For Metaphor” by Denis Donoghue: Summary and Critique

“The Motive for Metaphor” by Denis Donoghue first appeared in 2014 in the journal Raritan, Volume 33, Issue 3.

"The Motive For Metaphor" by Denis Donoghue: Summary and Critique

Introduction: “The Motive For Metaphor” by Denis Donoghue

“The Motive for Metaphor” by Denis Donoghue first appeared in 2014 in the journal Raritan, Volume 33, Issue 3. In this landmark essay, Donoghue explores the philosophical and poetic motivations behind the use of metaphor, drawing on classical rhetoric, literary criticism, and the metaphysical musings of poets such as Wallace Stevens and William Butler Yeats. Central to Donoghue’s argument is Quintilian’s notion that metaphor is both a natural and essential gift—something that lends grace and necessity to language by ensuring that nothing remains unnamed. The essay traces metaphor’s dual nature as both a linguistic necessity and an aesthetic desire, emphasizing its ability to reshape reality through imagination. Drawing from Stevens’s poetry, especially his eponymous poem “The Motive for Metaphor,” Donoghue argues that metaphor functions as a form of resistance—shrinking from the hard, fixed “primary noon” of reality in search of mutable truths and imaginative escape. The piece is notable in literary theory for its synthesis of rhetorical history, poetic analysis, and philosophical speculation. It positions metaphor not merely as ornamentation, but as a vital cognitive and spiritual operation, underscoring its central role in both literature and the human effort to know and name the world.

Summary of “The Motive For Metaphor” by Denis Donoghue

·  🔸 Metaphor as a Natural and Noble Act of Naming:
Drawing from Quintilian, Donoghue opens by stating that metaphor is a natural human gift:

“It is both a gift which Nature herself confers on us… [ensuring] that nothing goes without a name” (p.182) ✴
This framing treats metaphor not as a mere rhetorical flourish, but a fundamental linguistic and existential impulse.

·  🔸 Metaphor and the Liberty of the Mind:
Metaphor emerges from the freedom of the imagination, striving to give things their “proper names,” though often failing.

“The source of metaphor is the liberty of the mind among such words as there are” (p.184) ✴

·  🔸 Metaphor as Both Resource and Failure:
Metaphor reflects the inadequacies of language, and thus, its use becomes a noble but doomed attempt to make sense of a deficient world.

“Rhetoric… is a glorious failure, and the cry of metaphor is doomed” (p.184) ✴
“We cry out to change the world by giving things their proper names—but often we fail” (p.184) ✴

·  🔸 Allegory and Catachresis: Extensions of Metaphor:
Metaphor gives rise to allegory and to its extremes, catachresis—abused or “forced” metaphors that reveal linguistic limits.

“Allegory is its narrative form… Catachresis is the figure of its abuse” (p.185) ✴
“Something monstrous lurks in the most innocent of catachreses” – Paul de Man (p.185) ✴

·  🔸 Metaphor as Escape from Literal Reality:
According to Wallace Stevens (via Frye), the motive for metaphor is to escape the oppressive weight of objective reality, “the weight of primary noon.”

“The motive for metaphor, shrinking from / The weight of primary noon” – Stevens (p.186) ✴
“To defeat or evade the force of the world, it must resort to the imaginative capacity of the mind” (p.188) ✴

·  🔸 Interpretive Differences: Frye vs. Ransom:
Frye sees the metaphor as a bridge between mind and world; Ransom views it as a poetic solution to inexpressible moral feelings.

Frye: “The only genuine joy… is in those rare moments when you feel that… we are also a part of what we know” (p.187) ✴
Ransom: The metaphor avoids “the dreary searching of your own mind” (p.187) ✴

·  🔸 Stevens’s Hegelian Idealism and Artistic Desire:
Stevens’s poetic vision resonates with Hegel’s aesthetics, where art “lifts the inner and outer world into his spiritual consciousness.”

“The universal need for art… is man’s rational need to lift the inner and outer world into his spiritual consciousness” – Hegel (p.189) ✴

·  🔸 Art and Metaphor as Acts of Decreation:
Donoghue invokes Simone Weil and Picasso to show how metaphor contributes to a modern aesthetic of undoing the real, transforming or annihilating it.

“Modern reality is a reality of decreation” (p.191) ✴
“A poem is a horde of destructions” – Stevens (p.191) ✴

·  🔸 The Danger of Bad Metaphors:
Metaphors have the power to undermine themselves—a bad metaphor, Donoghue notes, can “murder” a good one.

“He must defy / The metaphor that murders metaphor” (p.191) ✴

·  🔸 Repetition, Association, and Stevens’s Reluctance to End:
Stevens’s poetry exhibits an additive and associative structure—where metaphors are strung together without clear hierarchy.

“One phrase is instructed to produce another by association” (p.192) ✴
“His sentences tend not to be decisive… he always sees a further possibility” (p.193) ✴

·  🔸 Shrinking from Fixity and Embracing Change:
Stevens shrinks from fixed truths, favoring the fluid, unstable states metaphor enables.

“A poet writes of twilight because he shrinks from noon-day” – Stevens (p.196) ✴

·  🔸 Resemblance as a Core Principle of Metaphor:
Stevens’s metaphors rely heavily on resemblance, which Donoghue critiques as too general to be philosophically sound.

“In some sense, all things resemble each other” – Stevens (p.198) ✴
“Similarity… is relative, variable and culture-dependent” – Nelson Goodman (p.199) ✴

·  🔸 Metaphor Intensifies Reality:
When it works, metaphor heightens our sense of reality, transforming the mundane into the sublime.

“It enhances the sense of reality, heightens it, intensifies it” (p.200) ✴
Example from Ecclesiastes: “The silver cord… the golden bowl… the wheel broken at the cistern” (p.200) ✴

·  🔸 Metaphor vs. Simile:
A metaphor demands total imaginative immersion, unlike simile which allows safe distance.

“A metaphor incurs resistance… and is indifferent to shame” (p.201) ✴

·  🔸 “X” as Final Resistance and Symbol of Limit:
Stevens’s “dominant X” represents the intractable world, the final, unchangeable reality metaphor fails to penetrate.

“Nothing in the poem defeats the final ‘X'” (p.206) ✴

·  🔸 No Final Word on Metaphor:
Donoghue concludes that Stevens’s relation to metaphor is inherently unstable. Each poetic mood shifts the meaning and function of metaphor.

“We can’t expect from Stevens a definitive statement about metaphor” (p.207) ✴
“In such seemings all things are. Metaphor… will do its transforming work another day” (p.207) ✴

Theoretical Terms/Concepts in “The Motive For Metaphor” by Denis Donoghue
📌 Term Explanation🔖 Reference/Quotation
🧠 MetaphorA natural, imaginative act of naming that both expands language and transforms perception.“It ensures that nothing goes without a name” (p.182)
📖 CatachresisA strained or improper metaphor that stretches or abuses meaning, yet remains rhetorically valid.“To speak of ‘forced metaphor’ is not to degrade its manifestations” (p.185)
🔍 ResemblanceStevens’s preferred foundation for metaphor, based on likeness; Donoghue critiques it as too vague to sustain theory.“In some sense, all things resemble each other” (p.198)
🌀 AllegoryAn extended metaphor that takes on narrative and moral form—what Fontanier calls “prolongée et continue.”“Allegory is its narrative form…” (p.185)
🎭 ProsopopoeiaA figure of speech in which non-human entities are personified—often emerging from overextended metaphors.“Catachresis is already turning into prosopopeia…” (p.185)
🔧 Concrete UniversalA Hegelian concept in which abstract ideas are made materially present; Ransom uses it to frame metaphor’s real-world function.“It becomes a Concrete Universal when it has been materialized…” (p.187)
🧬 ImaginationThe mental faculty that powers metaphor, allowing us to reshape reality through poetic transformation.“Metaphor creates a new reality…” (p.188)
💫 DecreationFrom Simone Weil: the spiritual undoing of created reality, which metaphor helps initiate as aesthetic escape.“Modern reality is a reality of decreation” (p.191)
🔗 SimilarityOften aligned with resemblance, but critiqued by Goodman for lacking objectivity and explanatory power in metaphor theory.“Similarity… is relative, variable and culture-dependent” (p.199)
🗣️ RhetoricA system of language arising from human insufficiency; metaphor is its central figure—both noble and doomed.“The axiom of all rhetoric is the principle of insufficient reason” (p.184)
🎇 TransformationThe creative operation by which metaphor changes how we see and name reality; tied to imagination and perception.“The object… turned freely in the hand…” (p.205)
🧩 The ‘X’Represents the unyielding, dominant force of the world or moral universals that metaphor cannot dissolve.“The vital, arrogant, fatal, dominant X” (p.186)
🖋️ Poetic AuthorityStevens often relinquishes control, letting language guide itself—challenging the notion of the poet as a final authority.“There are words / Better without an author…” (p.193)
🎨 Aesthetic EscapeMetaphor as a method of fleeing fixed, literal meaning in favor of poetic freedom and subjective truth.“Metaphor alone furnishes an escape” (p.191)
📜 IdealismA philosophical stance—prevalent in Stevens’s poetic moods—that assumes consciousness can transform external reality.“In most of his moods he was a Hegelian” (p.189)
Contribution of “The Motive For Metaphor” by Denis Donoghue to Literary Theory/Theories

  • 🧠 Metaphor as Cognitive and Ontological Tool
    Donoghue elevates metaphor beyond ornamentation, presenting it as essential to how humans name, understand, and exist within the world.

“It ensures that nothing goes without a name” – Quintilian (p.182)


  • 🌀 Poetic Language as Idealist Expression
    Stevens’s metaphoric thought aligns with Hegelian idealism, portraying metaphor as a spiritual act uniting inner consciousness and external reality.

“He woke in a metaphor: this was / A metamorphosis of paradise” (p.189)


  • 🎨 Metaphor as Aesthetic Resistance
    Metaphor becomes a form of imaginative protest against oppressive, fixed realities—”the weight of primary noon.”

“The motive for metaphor, shrinking from / The weight of primary noon” (p.186)


  • 🔧 Engagement with Classical Rhetorical Tradition
    Through references to Aristotle, Fontanier, and Quintilian, Donoghue reinterprets rhetorical devices like allegory, catachresis, and simile.

“Allegory is its narrative form… Catachresis is the figure of its abuse” (p.185)


  • 🧩 The ‘X’ as Limit of Language and Metaphor
    The “dominant X” in Stevens’s poem marks the threshold where metaphor fails—where language can no longer transform reality.

“Nothing in the poem defeats the final ‘X'” (p.206)


  • 🗣️ Rhetoric as Anthropological Necessity
    Donoghue, citing Blumenberg, reframes rhetoric not as persuasion but as an existential necessity driven by human lack and insufficiency.

“The axiom of all rhetoric is the principle of insufficient reason” (p.184)


  • 📖 Validation of Radical and ‘Abused’ Metaphors
    Defending even bizarre metaphors like “bisqued mountain,” Donoghue legitimizes catachresis as a productive, imaginative force.

“To speak of ‘forced metaphor’ is not to degrade its manifestations” (p.185)


  • 🔍 Critique of Resemblance as Metaphoric Ground
    Donoghue challenges Stevens’s assumption that resemblance is natural, invoking Nelson Goodman’s view that similarity is culturally constructed.

“Similarity… is relative, variable and culture-dependent” (p.199)


  • 🧬 Metaphor as Creative Ontology
    Metaphor does not just reflect reality—it makes it. It is a poietic act that creates new ways of seeing and being.

“Metaphor creates a new reality from which the original appears to be unreal” (p.188)


  • 📜 Interplay of Modernist Certainty and Postmodern Ambiguity
    Donoghue highlights Stevens’s shifting moods and refusal to settle on a singular metaphoric theory—an openness aligning with postmodern literary theory.

“We can’t expect from Stevens a definitive statement about metaphor” (p.207)

Examples of Critiques Through “The Motive For Metaphor” by Denis Donoghue
🔹 Symbol & Literary Work🧠 Critique via Metaphor Theory🔖 Reference from the Article
🦌 “In Memory of Eva Gore-Booth and Con Markiewicz” – W. B. YeatsDonoghue analyzes Yeats’s line “one a gazelle” to show metaphor as essence-transference, not mere comparison. It evokes a luminous unity between image and being.“The girl’s nature goes over into the nature of a gazelle as if both came from one luminous source” (p.183)
🌳 “The Motive for Metaphor” – Wallace StevensThis poem is Donoghue’s central text, used to explore how metaphor resists fixed meaning (“X”) and serves as aesthetic escape, yet ultimately fails to resolve existential or epistemological tensions.“Nothing in the poem defeats the final ‘X'” (p.206)
🥄 “Someone Puts a Pineapple Together” – Wallace StevensDonoghue critiques this poem for its bizarre metaphors, especially the “bisqued mountain,” as extreme cases of metaphor stretching meaning. They test the limits of metaphor as imaginative creation.“An Alp, a purple Southern mountain bisqued with the molten mixings of related things” (p.202)
🌞 “An Ordinary Evening in New Haven” – Wallace StevensDonoghue interprets Stevens’s metaphors (e.g., “chrysalis of all men”) as efforts to unite subjective perception and external form, though often open-ended and unresolved.“The self, the chrysalis of all men / Became divided in the leisure of blue day…” (p.203)
Criticism Against “The Motive For Metaphor” by Denis Donoghue
  • 🧩 Overreliance on Stevens’s Poetic Authority
    Donoghue hinges much of his theory on Wallace Stevens, potentially narrowing metaphor’s scope across diverse literary traditions.
    ➤ Critics might argue that using one poet’s temperament to frame a general theory of metaphor limits its broader applicability.

  • 🔄 Philosophical Inconsistency
    The essay oscillates between idealism and skepticism, invoking both Hegelian unity and postmodern ambiguity without fully reconciling the two.
    ➤ “We can’t expect from Stevens a definitive statement about metaphor” (p.207) may reflect this unresolved tension.

  • 🎨 Romanticization of Metaphor
    Donoghue tends to elevate metaphor to near-mystical status, emphasizing its aesthetic and existential powers while underplaying its structural or political dimensions.
    ➤ This limits metaphor’s role in critical discourse, including feminist, postcolonial, or ideological critiques.

  • 📏 Neglect of Formal and Linguistic Precision
    Critics may find Donoghue’s acceptance of vague terms like “resemblance” too generous, despite his citation of Nelson Goodman’s challenge to that notion.
    ➤ He critiques Stevens but doesn’t fully abandon slippery conceptual terrain, potentially undermining analytical rigor.

  • 🧠 Underuse of Contemporary Linguistic Theory
    While Donoghue engages with classical and continental thought, he gives minimal attention to modern cognitive or conceptual metaphor theory (e.g., Lakoff & Johnson).
    ➤ This makes the work more philosophically poetic than practically linguistic or interdisciplinary.

  • 🌐 Limited Cultural Range
    The examples and allusions are primarily Western, white, male, and canonical, raising concerns about inclusivity and broader relevance in global poetics.
    ➤ There’s little engagement with metaphor in non-Western traditions or contemporary marginalized voices.

Representative Quotations from “The Motive For Metaphor” by Denis Donoghue with Explanation
🔹 Quotation🧠 Explanation
“It ensures that nothing goes without a name”: a beautiful, caring motive.Metaphor satisfies a human need to name and give meaning—language becomes an act of care and completeness.
“Reality is a cliché from which we escape by metaphor.”Stevens sees metaphor as a means to liberate perception from the dullness of habitual reality.
“Metaphor creates a new reality from which the original appears to be unreal.”Metaphor doesn’t mirror the world—it transforms it, reshaping how we perceive and interact with reality.
“The motive for metaphor, shrinking from / The weight of primary noon.”Metaphor serves as a retreat from the harsh clarity of objective truth, favoring imaginative ambiguity.
“We live in a place / That is not our own and, much more, not ourselves.”This expresses existential dislocation, suggesting metaphor as a tool for self-integration and understanding.
“Metaphor alone furnishes an escape.”Ortega y Gasset’s concept, cited by Donoghue, emphasizes metaphor’s power as a vehicle of liberation from oppressive realism.
“A metaphor incurs resistance from our sense of absurdity and is indifferent to shame.”True metaphor challenges logic and comfort—it transforms language through audacity and creative force.
“The whole world is less susceptible to metaphor than a tea-cup is.”Stevens humorously points to the challenge of expressing large concepts through metaphor versus simple ones.
“Similarity does not explain metaphor or metaphorical truth.”Citing Goodman, Donoghue dismantles the naïve belief that resemblance underlies metaphor—it’s often the other way around.
“Too much as they are to be changed by metaphor, / Too actual…”Metaphor may sometimes fail—when reality is too concrete to be poetically transformed.
Suggested Readings: “The Motive For Metaphor” by Denis Donoghue
  1. DONOGHUE, DENIS. “The Motive for Metaphor.” The Hudson Review, vol. 65, no. 4, 2013, pp. 543–61. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/43489263. Accessed 14 Apr. 2025.
  2. O’Donoghue, Josie. “‘A Fling of Freedom.'” The Cambridge Quarterly, vol. 44, no. 1, 2015, pp. 69–77. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/43492472. Accessed 14 Apr. 2025.
  3. Donoghue, Denis. “The Motive for Metaphor.” Metaphor, Harvard University Press, 2014, pp. 182–208. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/j.ctt6wps2d.9. Accessed 14 Apr. 2025.